February 8, 2021, Christopher D. Carroll Bubbles
Denoting dividends as for a stock with a market price of
per share,
consider an investor who owns
shares at the beginning of period
yielding
total wealth
. Assuming the investor has no other source of
income (no labor income, for instance) the investor’s budget constraint will
be
| (1) |
which can be rearranged to indicate how many shares the investor will own next period, as a function of this period’s wealth and consumption:
| (2) |
If this investor’s only goal is to maximize the present discounted utility of
consumption and the investor uses a discount factor of then we
have
| (3) |
with FOC
| (4) |
Now suppose that the investor is risk neutral () so that
; (4) becomes
| (5) |
Of course, similar logic can be employed to show that
| (6) |
and we can use the law of iterated expectations to substitute repeatedly, obtaining
| (7) |
We usually assume the ‘no-bubbles’ condition that says that
. In this case it is clear that the equilibrium
price must equal the present discounted value of dividends:
| (8) |
Suppose now that dividends are expected to grow by a constant factor
henceforth. In that case we have
| (9) |
which is known as the “Gordon formula.” The tricky thing in applying
the formula is to know what to assume for and
. The interest
rate
should be the interest rate ‘appropriate’ for discounting risky
quantities. The usual assumption is that
where
is the rate of
return on perfectly safe (riskfree) assets and
is the rate-of-return
premium that people demand as compensation for the risk inherent in future
dividends.
Suppose that a security price at time ,
, can be written as the
rational expectation of some ‘fundamental value’
conditional on
information available at time
(the usual example of the ‘fundamental
value’ in question is the present discounted value of dividends). Then we
have
| (10) |
The same formula holds in period :
| (11) |
Then the expectation of the change in the price over the next period is
| (12) |
because any information known at time must be known at time
and so
the only thing that should cause a change in prices should be the arrival of new
information that was not known at time
.
Note, however, that we simply assumed the no-bubbles condition - we did not
justify it with economic logic. Consider the following candidate process for
:
| (13) |
That is, price is equal to the fundamental price plus a ‘bubble’ term
which grows nonstochastically at rate
from period to period.
(Here we will assume that the risk premium
is zero, which would be
true in equilibrium for risk-neutral consumers). The question at hand
is whether this equation satisfies the first order condition (5). We can
show that it does by starting with the formula for
and working
backwards:
| (14) |
In words, this says that the first order condition has an infinite number of
solutions of the form . Thus, nothing about the logic of the
problem thus far rules out a rational deterministic bubble, which is a bubble
whose size grows at the rate of interest forever. Thus, in principle any level
of the stock price is possible at period
; all that the theory implies
is that if a bubble exists, its value must rise by a factor
in every
period.
Blanchard (1989) considers another possible candidate process for :
| (15) |
| (16) |
Roll equation (15) forward one period, and take its expectation as of time
:
| (17) |
Thus, the model allows stochastic bubbles which, during the period of their inflation, rise at a rate that is enough faster than the gross interest rate to exactly compensate shareholders (in expected value terms) for their expected capital loss when the bubble collapses.
Note that the probability that the bubble has burst by time is the
probability that it bursts in
plus the probability that it bursts in
given that it did not burst in
, and so on:
| (18) |
As we let , then since
, the RHS of (18) converges to
. Thus, the probability that the bubble has burst by time
, as
goes to infinity, approaches one.
Note that the bubble term in equation (13) rises without bound. It turns out
that this fact rules out negative bubbles. To see why, note that if is negative
and if the fundamental price
is bounded, then eventually
grows large
enough so that the predicted price of a share is negative. But if share prices were
negative, people could make themselves better off by simply throwing away their
stock certificates. Thus, the restriction that prices must be positive rules out
negative bubbles.
Bubbles can also be ruled out if there is a maximum possible price
that the asset can have. Consider, for example, the question of whether
there can be a bubble on the price of diamonds. Suppose that there is a
fixed supply of natural diamonds in existence, but suppose that new
artificial diamonds can be made at some price , that is diamonds
can be made at a cost 4 times higher than the current market price.
But if there is a bubble, then it will imply that eventually the market
price would exceed
. At that point, nobody will be willing to pay
for natural diamonds, so the bubble’s price cannot keep rising
beyond
. Thus, rational bubbles are ruled out for assets which are
reproducible.
We assumed, in deriving these results, that the investor’s utility function was linear. It is more difficult to justify rational bubbles in an economy with risk averse investors.
There are also some general equilibrium arguments against bubbles, which basically boil down to the observation that if the value of the bubble is growing forever, its size will eventually exceed the size of the entire capital stock, and in that case productive capital will have been driven to zero because everybody owns the bubble instead of capital, which can’t make sense.
Blanchard, Olivier J. (1989): “Speculative Bubbles, Crashes, and Rational Expectations,” Economics Letters, 3, 387–389, http://ideas.repec.org/a/eee/ecolet/v3y1979i4p387-389.html.