February 7, 2021, Christopher D. Carroll Habits
Consider a consumer whose goal at date is to solve the
problem1
| (1) |
where is the habit stock, and all other variables are as usually defined.
The DBC is
| (2) |
However, when habits affect utility we must also specify a process that describes how habits evolve over time. Our assumption will be:
| (3) |
Bellman’s equation for this problem is therefore
| (4) |
To clarify the workings of the Envelope theorem in the case with two state variables, let’s define a function
| (5) |
and define the function as the choice of
that solves the
maximization (4), so that we have
| (6) |
The first order condition for (4) with respect to is (dropping arguments for
brevity and denoting the derivative of
with respect to
at time
as
):
| (7) |
or, equivalently,
| (8) |
The intuition is as follows. Note first that if utility is not affected by habits,
then and equation (8) reduces to the usual first order condition for
consumption, which tells us that increasing consumption by
today and
reducing it by
in the next period must not change expected discounted
utility. With habits, an increase in consumption today has a consequence beyond
its effect on tomorrow’s resources
: tomorrow’s habit stock will be changed
as well. An increase in consumption today of size
increases the size
of the habit stock which tomorrow’s consumption is compared to, and
therefore reduces tomorrow’s utility by an amount corresponding to the
marginal utility of higher habits tomorrow
. Since
is negative
(higher habits make utility lower), this tells us that the RHS of equation
(8) will be a larger positive number than it would be without habits.
This means that the level of
that satisfies the first order condition
will be a lower number (higher marginal utility) than before. Hence,
habits increase the willingness to delay spending, and increase the saving
rate.
Note that the first order condition also implies that
| (9) |
when evaluated at .
Now consider the total derivative of with respect to
.
(To reduce clutter, I will write
as
). The chain rule
tells us that
| (10) |
so we have that
| (11) |
The Envelope theorem is the shortcut way to obtain this conclusion. The
clearest way to use the theorem is by taking the partial derivatives of the
function with respect to each of its three arguments, using the Chain
Rule to take into account the possible dependency of
and
on
:
| (12) |
where the Envelope theorem is what tells you that the term is equal to
zero because you are evaluating the function at
(and
is zero by the assumed structure of the problem in which
is
predetermined).
Now writing out , (12) becomes
| (13) |
which the envelope theorem says is equivalent to
| (14) |
There is a potentially confusing thing about doing it this way, however: when
you reach an expression like (13) it is tempting to think to yourself as follows:
“ is a function of
, and
is also indirectly a function of
, so
the chain rule tells me that when I take the derivative in (13) I need to keep
track of these.” In fact, you must treat
and
as zero here.
The reason is that this is a partial derivative with respect to
. The
dependence of
(and indirectly
) on
has already been taken
care of in the two terms in (12) that were equal to zero. The confusion
here is caused largely by the fact that partial differentiation is an area
where standard mathematical notation is basically confusing and poorly
chosen.2
The shortest way to obtain the end result is, as in the single variable
problem, to start with Bellman’s equation and take the partial derivative
with respect to directly (treating the problem as though
were a
constant):
| (15) |
Whichever way you do it, substituting (14) into the FOC equation (8) gives
| (16) |
The intuition for this is as follows. The marginal value of wealth must be equal
to the marginal value associated with a tiny bit more consumption. In the
presence of habits, the extra consumption yields extra utility today but
affects value next period by
(which is a negative number), the
discounted consequence of which from today’s perspective is the
term.
In a problem with two state variables, the Envelope theorem can be applied to each state (and indeed in general must be applied in order to solve the model).
Again let’s start the brute force way by working through the total derivative of
. For this problem, the total derivative (again denoting
as
) is:
| (17) |
so we have
| (18) |
Turning now to more direct use of the envelope theorem, the Chain Rule tells us
|
while the Envelope theorem once again says at
so
we obtain
| (19) |
since appears directly only in the
part of
. And once
again, the shortest way to the answer is to treat
as though it were a constant
in the value function, which yields
| (20) |
From (16) this implies that
| (21) |
Roll this equation forward one period and substitute into equation (14) to obtain:
| (22) |
Note that if so that habits have no effect on utility, (22) again
is solved by the standard time-separable Euler equation.
Now assume that the utility function takes the specific form
| (23) |
which implies derivatives of
| (24) |
Substituting these into equation (22) we obtain,
| (25) |
Now assume that there is a solution in which marginal utility of consumption
grows at a constant rate over time, and substitute into (25)
| (26) |
so marginal utility grows at rate . Note that if we assume
so
that habits do not matter, we again obtain the standard result that
.
Now make the final assumption that , implying of course
that
. Equation (26) can be rewritten
| (27) |
Now expand
where (29) follows from (28) because
and
, and (32) follows from (31)
because for small
and
.
Substituting (32) into (27) gives
|
Thus, this formulation of habit formation implies that the growth rate of consumption is serially correlated.
Carroll, Christopher D. (2000): “Solving Consumption Models with Multiplicative Habits,” Economics Letters, 68(1), 67–77, http://econ.jhu.edu/people/ccarroll/HabitsEconLett.pdf.