cAndCwithStickyE
_____________________________________________________________________________________
Abstract
Macroeconomic models often invoke consumption “habits” to explain the
substantial persistence of aggregate consumption growth. But a large literature
has found no evidence of habits in the (vastly larger) microeconomic datasets
that measure the behavior of individual households. We show that the apparent
conflict can be explained by a model in which consumers have accurate
knowledge of their personal circumstances but ‘sticky expectations’ about the
macroeconomy. In our model, the persistence of aggregate consumption growth
reflects consumers’ imperfect attention to aggregate shocks. Our proposed degree
of (macro) inattention has negligible utility costs, because aggregate
shocks constitute only a tiny proportion of the uncertainty that consumers
face. In contrast with models in the existing literature, our model is
consistent with both micro and macro stylized facts about consumption
dynamics.
Consumption, Sticky Expectations, Habits, Inattention, Imperfect Information
D83, D84, E21, E32
PDF: | http://www.econ2.jhu.edu/people/ccarroll/papers/cAndCwithStickyE.pdf |
Web: | http://www.econ2.jhu.edu/people/ccarroll/papers/cAndCwithStickyE/ |
Archive: | http://www.econ2.jhu.edu/people/ccarroll/papers/cAndCwithStickyE.zip |
Slides: | Versions to View or Print |
Toolkit: | http://github.com/Econ-ARK/HARK |
1Carroll: Department of Economics, Johns Hopkins University, http://www.econ2.jhu.edu/people/ccarroll/, ccarroll@jhu.edu 2Crawley: Department of Economics, Johns Hopkins University, ecrawle2@jhu.edu 3Slacalek: DG Research, European Central Bank, http://www.slacalek.com/, jiri.slacalek@ecb.europa.eu 4Tokuoka: Ministry of Finance, Japan, kiichi.tokuoka@mof.go.jp 5White: Department of Economics, University of Delaware, mnwecon@udel.edu
Starting with Campbell and Deaton [1989], the macroeconomics, finance, and international economics literatures have established that aggregate consumption exhibits ‘excess smoothness’ compared with the benchmark Hall [1978] random walk model of consumption.2 Over the past two decades many papers in these fields have responded to this problem by incorporating ‘habit formation’ in the utility function of a representative agent.
This literature typically measures excess smoothness with a parameter conventionally
labeled as the ‘habit formation coefficient’ (which we denote as ). A recent
comprehensive meta-analysis of 597 published estimates (Havranek et al. [2017])
reports that studies based on macro data find that
on average; see
Figure 1.3
If habits are a true structural characteristic of people’s utility functions, we
should see their effects microeconomic data as well as macroeconomic aggregates.
But empirical studies using household-level data strongly reject the existence of
habits of the magnitude necessary to explain aggregate consumption dynamics.
The modal estimate from Havranek et al. [2017]’s survey of the micro
literature is a ‘habit’ parameter of 0; the mean estimate is about 0.1 (see
Figure 1).4
Even among studies that have found evidence against the random walk proposition in
micro data,5
few claim to have found more than a few percentage points’ worth of
household-level spending growth to be predictable at any measured horizon.
Roughly speaking, the predictability of aggregate spending growth is around an
order of magnitude larger than predictability of household-level spending growth
(say, 0.30 versus 0.03 in an adjusted sense).
We propose a simple solution to this puzzle. Instead of having consumption habits, microeconomic consumers experience a modest informational friction: Not everybody instantaneously notices all macroeconomic developments. Instead, households’ macroeconomic expectations are “sticky,” as in Mankiw and Reis [2002] and Carroll [2003]. Specifically, while each consumer perfectly (‘frictionlessly’) perceives his own personal circumstances (employment status, wage rate, income received, etc), consumers’ information about macroeconomic quantities like aggregate productivity growth arrives only occasionally (as in the Calvo model of firms’ price updating).
Consumption sluggishness a la Campbell and Deaton [1989] arises as follows. As in the standard (frictionless) setup, sticky-expectations households perfectly observe their market resources (wealth, debt, etc) and income. However, a consumer whose beliefs about the state of the aggregate economy are out of date will behave in the ways that would have been macroeconomically appropriate (for the consumer’s currently observed level of wealth etc) at the time of their last (and possibly out-of-date) perception of macroeconomic circumstances. The model thus generates a lag in the response of aggregate spending to aggregate developments; the amount of sluggishness will depend on the frequency with which consumers update. When our model’s updating frequency is calibrated to match conventional estimates of the degree of inattention measured using expectations data on other aggregate variables (e.g., inflation expectations), the model’s implications for the persistence in aggregate consumption growth match well the estimates of the ‘excess smoothness’ of consumption growth in the macro literature.
Despite aggregate sluggishness, at the level of individual households, high-frequency consumption growth has little predictability. This can be reconciled with aggregate smoothness because the rationally appropriate contribution of the consumer’s perception of the macroeconomic environment to their individual spending choices is swamped by the importance of fluctuations in idiosyncratic components of income which we assume consumers have no difficulty observing (and to which we assume they are perfectly attentive).6
In our model, the sticky updating of beliefs about the aggregate economy takes the same form (and has the same magnitude) as proposed in Carroll [2003] as a microfoundation for the Mankiw and Reis [2002] model. An advantage compared to those papers is that because we are using an optimizing model, we are able to calculate an explicit utility cost of stickiness. Consistent with a theme in the literature on inattentiveness all the way back to Akerlof and Yellen [1985], we find that the utility penalty from inattention is low, so that, under our calibrated parameters, our consumers would not be willing to pay much for even the most perfect information about the macroeconomic state: They would be willing to pay roughly one two-thousandth of their lifetime income to be perfectly informed in every future period of their lifetime.
Our results are essentially the same in a partial equilibrium model (in which factor prices are constant) and a heterogeneous-agents DSGE model with aggregate shocks (which affect factor prices).7 Data simulated from our models reproduce what we take to be the main stylized facts about individual and aggregate consumption dynamics.
When estimated on simulated individual data (corresponding to microeconomic evidence), regressions in the spirit of Hall [1978] and Campbell and Mankiw [1989] find that consumption growth exhibits little persistence. This result is essentially identical across all variants of our models: partial or general equilibrium, with or without inattention. It comports well with the conclusions of a micro literature that was already large when Deaton [1992] surveyed it and has remained consistent in finding little persistence. In this respect (and all others), the micro implications of the model are standard for models of this type (with uninsurable uncertainty as well as precautionary saving and perhaps liquidity constraints), which have been extensively studied in the micro literature.8
We then analyze Hall [1978]/Campbell and Mankiw [1989] regressions with simulated aggregate data. Thanks to the law of large numbers, the idiosyncratic shocks that dominate the household data cancel out upon aggregation, leaving only the residual systematic factors, which generate the much greater predictability in aggregate than in idiosyncratic data. Campbell and Mankiw [1989] proposed that such predictability arises because some people just spend all their income, and income growth is predictable. The habit formation literature has argued instead that predictability reflected the sluggishness of consumption growth itself. Horserace regressions that pit these two possibilities against each other produce a clear winner: Almost all of the predictability of consumption growth is explained by its correlation with lagged consumption growth; only a small portion comes from the predictable component of aggregate income growth – both in the data and in our model.
After a brief review of the extensive relevant literature, we begin explaining our ideas with a ‘toy model’ (section 3) in which the key mechanisms can be derived analytically, thanks to extreme simplifying assumptions like quadratic utility and constant factor prices. We next (section 4) present the full versions of our models, which abide by the more realistic assumptions (CRRA utility, aggregate as well as individual shocks, time varying factor prices, etc) that have become conventional respectively in the micro and macro literatures.
After calibrating the model (section 5), we describe the stylized facts from both the micro and macro literatures that we argue need to be explained by a good microfounded macroeconomic model of consumption, and show that all of the various versions of our model (partial versus general equilibrium, etc) robustly reproduce those facts (section 6). This robustness indicates that our results are not a fragile implication of any highly specific framework but instead flow from the underlying structure of inattention that is the common element across all versions of our model (including the quadratic utility ‘toy model’ where the consequences can be seen most clearly). We then (section 7) calculate how much a fully informed consumer would be willing to pay at birth to enjoy instantaneous and perfect knowledge of aggregate developments as they live their life (not much, it turns out).
With our model’s quantitative results in hand, we describe the quantitative and qualitative differences between our model and the other ‘imperfect information’ approaches to explaining aggregate consumption smoothness that have been explored in the prior literature (section 8). Our conclusion suggests directions for future research.
No review of the empirical literature is needed; Havranek et al. [2017] have done an admirable job. Our only critique is that they have followed much of the prior literature in casually referring to the parameter of interest as the ‘habit coefficient.’ A better choice would have been to call it the ‘excess smoothness’ coefficient; ours is not the first paper to suggest that habits are not the only possible explanation for why consumption growth might be too smooth (compared to the Hall [1978] benchmark).
Our ‘sticky expectations’ approach is related to several strands of the burgeoning literature on models of imperfect information processing. A major strand in that literature is models of ‘rational inattention’ in the spirit of Sims [2003], in which agents have a limited ability to pay attention and allocate it optimally, recently embodied (for example) in the work of Maćkowiak and Wiederholt [2015]. They study a DSGE model with inattentive consumers and firms using a simple New Keynesian framework in which they replace all sources of slow adjustment (habit formation, Calvo pricing and wage setting) with rational inattention. The setup with rational inattention can match the sluggish responses observed in aggregate data, in response both to monetary policy shocks and to technology shocks.
A challenge to this approach has been the extraordinary complexity of solving models that aim to work out the full implications of the fact that everyone else is working out the full implications of the fact that everyone else is rationally inattentive.9 In response, Gabaix [2014] has recently proposed a framework that is much simpler than the full rational inattention framework of Sims [2003], but aims to capture much of its essence. This approach is relatively new, and while it does promise to be more tractable than the full-bore Simsian rational inattention framework, even the simplified Gabaix approach would be formidably difficult to embed in a model with a rich treatment of transitory and persistent income shocks, precautionary motives and other complexities entailed in modern models of microeconomic consumption decisions. It would be similarly challenging to determine how to apply the approaches of Woodford [2002] or Morris and Shin [2006] to our question.10
Another way to dial back the complexity of the rational inattention approach is to radically simplify the model’s assumptions about decisionmaker’s problem. In that spirit Reis [2006a] considers a model in which consumers with a linear consumption function and a conveniently simple environment optimally choose to be inattentive because of explicit (fixed monetary) costs of attention.11 In this framework, Reis [2006a] is able to calculate an explicit analytical formula for the tradeoff between the disutility from the increase in uncertainty caused by inattention, and the monetary savings due to infrequent payment of the cost of information. Reis shows that in his model, inattention is manifested in the fact the his consumers only gather new information (and therefore only update their consumption) at fixed intervals whose length depends on the cost of obtaining information versus the costs of remaining ignorant.
One of our objectives is to faithfully match microeconomic data. In such data there is incontrovertible evidence—most recently from millions of datapoints from the Norwegian population registry examined by Fagereng et al. [2017]—that the consumption function is not linear. It is concave, as the general theory suggests (Carroll and Kimball [1996]), and this concavity matters greatly for matching the main micro facts. There is also nothing that looks either like the Reis model’s prediction that there will be extended periods in which consumption does not change at all, nor its prediction that there will be occasional periods in which it moves a lot (at dates of adjustment) and then remains constant at that newer level for some extended period. This critique applies generically to models that incorporate a convex cost of adjustment—whether to the consumer’s stock of information (Reis [2006a]) or to the level of consumption as in Chetty and Szeidl [2016]. All such models imply counterfactually ‘jerky’ behavior of spending at the microeconomic level.12
To better match the micro data, we use the now-conventional microeconomic formulation in which utility takes the Constant Relative Risk Aversion form and uncertainty is calibrated to match micro estimates. Our assumption that consumers can perfectly observe the idiosyncratic components of their income allows us to use essentially the same solution methods as in the substantial recent literature exploring models of this kind; our assumption that macroeconomic expectations are sticky makes no material difference to the solution of the model.13 Implementing the state of the art in the micro literature adds a great deal of complexity and precludes a closed form solution for consumption like the one used by Reis; its virtue is that the model is quantitatively plausible enough that, for example, it might actually be usable by policymakers who wanted to assess the likely dynamics entailed by alternative fiscal policy options.
Given our choice to embrace the challenge of matching micro data, it was essential to keep the rest of the model as simple as possible, in the spirit of Akerlof and Yellen [1985], Cochrane [1991], Mankiw and Reis [2002] and as forcefully advocated by Browning and Crossley [2001]. In pursuit of such simplicity, we adopt the Calvo [1983]-like framework of Carroll [2003] in which updating is a Poisson event.14
Inattention is not the only alternative to habits as an explanation for excess smoothness. Information itself can be imperfect, even for a perfectly attentive consumer. The seminal work contemplating this possibility was by Muth [1960], whose most direct descendant in the consumption literature is Pischke [1995] (building also on Lucas [1973]). The idea is that (perfectly attentive) consumers face a signal extraction problem in determining whether a shock to income is transitory or permanent. When a permanent shock occurs, the immediate adjustment to the shock is only partial, since agents’ best guess is that the shock is partly transitory and partly permanent. With the right calibration, such a model could in principle explain any amount of excess smoothness. But we argue that when a model of this kind is calibrated to the actual empirical data, it generates only a modest amount of excess smoothness, far less than exhibited by the empirical data.
Moving from theory to evidence, there is an interesting and growing literature that uses expectations data from surveys in an attempt to directly measure sluggishness in expectations dynamics.15 For example, Coibion and Gorodnichenko [2015] find that the implied degree of information rigidity in inflation expectations is high, with an average duration of six to seven months between information updates. Fuhrer [2017b] and Fuhrer [2017a] find that even for professional forecasters, forecast revisions are explainable using lagged information, which would not be the case under perfect information processing.
Here we briefly introduce concepts and notation, and motivate the key result
using a simple framework with quadratic utility. We start with the classic
Hall [1978] random walk model, with the standard assumption of time separable
utility and geometric discounting by factor . Overall wealth
(the sum of
human and nonhuman wealth) evolves according to the dynamic budget
constraint
With no informational frictions, the usual derivations lead to the standard Euler equation:
where
Now suppose consumers update their information about , and therefore their
behavior, only occasionally. A consumer who updates in period
obtains
precisely the same information that a consumer in a frictionless model would
receive, forms the same expectations, and makes the same choices. Nonupdaters,
however, behave as though their former expectations had actually come true
(since by definition these are the persons who have learned nothing to disconfirm
their prior beliefs). For example, consider a consumer who updates in periods
and
but not between. Designating
as the consumer’s perception of
wealth:
The economy is populated by consumers indexed by , distributed uniformly
along the unit interval. Aggregate (or equivalently, per capita) consumption
is
Whether the consumer at location updates in period
is determined by
the realization of the binary random variable
, which takes the value 1 if
consumer
updates in period
and 0 otherwise. Each period’s updaters are
chosen randomly such that a constant proportion
update in each period:
Aggregate consumption is the population-weighted average of per-capita
consumption of updaters and nonupdaters
:
This is the mechanism behind the exercises presented in Section 6. While the details of the informational friction is different in the more realistic models we will set up in Section 4, the same logic and quantitative result holds: the serial correlation of consumption growth approximately equals the proportion of non-updaters.
Note further that the model does not introduce any explicit reason that consumption growth should be related to the predictable component of income growth a la Campbell and Mankiw [1989]. In a regression of consumption growth on the predictable component of income growth (and nothing else), the coefficient on income growth would entirely derive from whatever correlation predictable income growth might have with lagged consumption growth. This is the pattern we will find below, both in our theoretical and our empirical work.
One of the lessons of the consumption literature after Hall [1978] is that his
simplifying assumptions (quadratic utility, perfect capital markets, ) are
far from innocuous; more plausible assumptions can lead to very different
conclusions. In particular, a host of persuasive theoretical and empirical
considerations has led to the now-standard assumption of constant relative risk
aversion utility,
When utility is not quadratic, solution of
the model requires specification of the exact stochastic structure of the income
and transition processes.
Below, we present two models that will be used to simulate the economy under frictionless and sticky expectations. First, we specify a small open economy (or partial equilibrium) model with a rich and empirically realistic calibration of idiosyncratic and aggregate risk but exogenous interest rates and wages. Second, we extend the SOE model to a heterogeneous agents dynamic stochastic general equilibrium (closed-economy) model that endogenizes factor returns, at the cost of a more burdensome computational task.17
Several features are common across all our models. A continuum of agents care
about expected lifetime utility derived from CRRA preferences over a unitary
consumption good; they geometrically discount future utility flows by
discount factor . These agents inelastically supply one unit of labor,
and their only decision in each period
is how to divide their market
resources
between consumption
and saving in a single asset
.
We assume agents are Blanchard [1985] “perpetual youth” consumers:
They have a constant probability of death
between periods, and
upon death they are are immediately replaced, while their assets are
distributed among surviving households in proportion to the recipient’s
wealth.
Output is produced by a Cobb–Douglas technology using capital and
(effective) labor
; capital depreciates at rate
immediately after producing
output, leaving portion
intact, and as usual the effectiveness of labor
depends on the level of aggregate labor productivity.
We represent both aggregate and idiosyncratic productivity levels as having both transitory and permanent components. Large literatures have found that this representation is difficult to improve upon much in either context, and the simplicity of this description yields considerable benefits both in the tractability of the model, and in making its mechanics as easy to understand as possible.
In more detail, aggregate permanent labor productivity grows by factor
, subject to mean one iid aggregate permanent shocks
, so the aggregate
productivity state evolves according to:
![]() | (3) |
The productivity growth factor follows a bounded random walk, as in (for
example) Edge et al. [2007], which is part of a literature whose aim is to capture
in a simple statistical way the fact that underlying rates of productivity growth
seem to vary substantially over time (e.g., fast in the 1950s, slow in the
1970s and 1980s, moderate in the 1990s, and so on; see also Jorgenson
et al. [2008]).18
We introduce these slow-moving productivity growth rates not just for realism
but also because we need to perform, in our simulated data, exercises like those
Campbell and Mankiw [1989] performed in empirical data, in which
consumption growth is regressed on the component of income growth that was
predictable using data lagged several quarters. We therefore need a model in
which there is some predictability in income growth several quarters in the
future.
The transitory component of productivity in any period is represented by a
mean-one variable , so the overall level of aggregate productivity in a given
period is
.
Similarly, each household has an idiosyncratic labor productivity level ,
which (conditional on survival) evolves according to:
![]() | (4) |
and like their aggregate counterparts, idiosyncratic
permanent productivity shocks are mean one iid
().19
Total labor productivity for the individual is determined by the interaction of
transitory idiosyncratic (
), transitory aggregate (
), permanent
idiosyncratic
, and permanent aggregate
factors. When the
household supplies one unit of labor, this contributes effective labor equal
to:
For understanding the decisions of an individual consumer in a frictionless (i.e.,
perfect information) world the aggregate and idiosyncratic transitory shocks can
be combined into a single overall transitory shock indicated by the boldface ,
and the aggregate and idiosyncratic levels of permanent income can be
combined as
(likewise, the combined permanent shock is boldface
). However, a key feature of the models used here is that a
household does not necessarily know the true value of the aggregate
productivity state variables
, as they might not have (stochastically)
observed it in the current period. Instead, each household has perceptions
about the aggregate state
. Our key behavioral assumption is
twofold:
Given the assumption that productivity growth follows a random walk, the
second part of the behavioral assumption says that an agent who last observed
the true aggregate state
periods ago perceives:
![]() | (6) |
That is, our assumed random walk in productivity growth
means that the household believes that aggregate productivity
has grown at the last observed growth rate for the past
periods.20
For households who observed the true aggregate state this period,
and
thus (6) says that
. The household perceives that their
overall permanent productivity level is
.
Households in our models always correctly observe the level of all real
variables—they are able to read their bank statement and paycheck. But (as will
be shown below) consumers’ optimal behavior in the frictionless model depends
on the ratios of those real variables to productivity. That is, for some state
variable (like market wealth), the optimal choice would depend on
,
where our definition of nonboldface
reflects our notational convention that
when a level variable has been normalized by the corresponding measure of
productivity, it loses its boldness. The same applies for aggregate variables
.
When a household’s perception of productivity differs from actual
productivity, we denote the perceived ratio as, e.g.,
where
the last equality reflects our assumption that the household perceives the
idiosyncratic component of their productivity
without error.
The behavior of a ‘sticky expectations’ consumer thus differs from that of a frictionless consumer only to the extent that the ‘sticky expectations’ consumer’s perception of aggregate productivity is out of date.
Infinitely-lived households with a productivity process like (4) would generate a
nonergodic distribution of idiosyncratic productivity—as individuals
accumulated ever more shocks to their permanent productivities, those
productivities would spread out indefinitely with time. To avoid this
inconvenience, we make the Blanchard [1985] assumption: Each consumer faces
a constant probability of mortality of (with complementary survival
probability
). We track death events using a binary indicator:
![]() |
We refer to this henceforth as a ‘replacement’ event, since the consumer who dies
is replaced by an unrelated newborn who happens to inhabit the same location
on the number line. The ex ante probability of death is identical for each
consumer, so that the aggregate mass of consumers who are replaced is time
invariant at .
Under the assumption that ‘newborns’ have the population average productivity level of
, the population mean of the idiosyncratic component of permanent income is always
.21
Our earlier equation (4) for the idiosyncratic productivity transition rule
for the inhabitant of location
on the number line is thus adjusted
to:22
![]() |
Along with its productivity level, the household’s primary state variable when
the consumption decision is made is the level of market resources , which
captures both current period labor income
(the wage rate times the
household’s effective labor supply) and the resources that come from the agent’s
capital stock
(the value of the capital itself plus the value of the capital
income it yields):
![]() | (7) |
The transition process for is broken up, for convenience of analysis, into
three steps. ‘Assets’ at the end of the period are market resources minus
consumption:
![]() |
where the first row’s division of by the survival probability
reflects
returns to survivors from the Blanchardian insurance scheme in which the dying
agents’ assets are distributed to the survivors. More compactly we can write:
The foregoing assumptions permit straightforward aggregation of individual-level variables. Aggregate capital is the population integral of (9):
![]() | (10) |
The third equality holds because and
is
independent of
. Because
aggregate labor supply is
Aggregate market resources can be written as per-capita resources of the
survivors times their population mass , plus per-capita resources of the
newborns times their population mass
:
The productivity-normalized version of (12) says that
![]() | (13) |
Because the households in our model do not necessarily observe the true aggregate productivity level, their perception of normalized aggregate market resources is
![]() | (14) |
We will sometimes refer to the factor as the household’s ‘productivity
misperception,’ the scaling factor between actual and perceived market
resources. As discussed below, this same misperception factor applies to
individual market resources as well.
Our first realistic model considers a small open economy with perfect
international capital mobility, so that factor prices and
are exogenously
determined (at constant values
and
). These assumptions permit a
partial equilibrium analysis using only the solution to the individual
households’ problem. The frictionless consumer’s state variables are simply
. Because we assume that the sticky expectations consumer
behaves according to the decision rules that are optimal for the frictionless
consumer but using perceived rather than true values of the state variables, we
need only to solve for the frictionless solution.
The household’s problem in levels can be written in Bellman form as:23
Our assumption that the aggregate and idiosyncratic productivity
levels both reflect a combination of transitory and purely permanent
components now permits us to make a transformation that considerably
simplifies analysis and solution of the model: When the utility function is
in the CRRA class, the problem can be simplified by dividing by
while converting to normalized variables as above (e.g.,
).24
This yields the normalized form of the problem, which has only
and
as
state variables:
Defining , the main requirement for this problem to have a solution is an impatience
condition:25
Designating the converged normalized consumption function that solves (16) as
, the level of consumption for the frictionless consumer can be
obtained26
from
Following the same notation as in the motivating Section 3, we define an indicator
variable for whether household updates their perception to the true aggregate state in
period
:27
![]() |
The Bernoulli random variable is iid for each household each period, with
a probability
of returning 1. Consistent with (6), household beliefs about the
aggregate state evolve according to:
![]() | (17) |
Under the assumption that consumers treat their belief about the
aggregate state as if it were the truth, the relevant inputs for the normalized
consumption function are the household’s perceived normalized
market resources
and perceived aggregate
productivity growth
. The household chooses their level of consumption by:
![]() | (18) |
The behavior of the ‘sticky expectations’ consumer converges to that of the
frictionless consumer as ; conveniently, we can use the same simulation
code for both kinds of consumers by simply setting
to generate the
behavior of the frictionless economy.
Because households in our model never misperceive the level of their own market
resources (), they can never choose consumption that would violate the budget
constraint.28
But their misperceptions of aggregate permanent income do cause them to make
systematic errors. See below for calculations showing that for the value of
that we estimate, those errors are very small.
Our second model relaxes the simplifying assumption of a frictionless global
capital market. In this closed economy, factor prices and
are determined
in the usual way from the aggregate production function and aggregate
state variables, including the stochastic aggregate shocks, putting the
model in the (small, but growing) class of heterogeneous agent DSGE
models.
We make the standard assumption that markets are competitive, and so factor
prices are the marginal product of (effective) labor and capital respectively.
Denoting capital’s share as , so that
, this yields the usual
wage and interest rates:
An agent’s relevant state variables at the time of the consumption
decision include the levels of household and aggregate market resources
, as well as household and aggregate labor productivity
and the aggregate growth rate
. We assume that agents correctly
understand the operation of the economy, including the production and
shock processes, and have beliefs about aggregate saving—how aggregate
market resources
become aggregate assets
(equivalently, next
period’s aggregate capital
). Following Krusell and Smith [1998] and
Carroll et al. [2017], we assume that households believe that the aggregate
saving rule is linear in logs, conditional on the current aggregate growth
rate:
![]() | (20) |
The growth-rate-conditional parameters and
are exogenous to the
individual’s (partial equilibrium) optimization problem, but are endogenous to
the general equilibrium of the economy. Taking the aggregate saving rule
as given, the household’s problem can be written in Bellman form
as:29
As in the SOE model, the household’s problem can be normalized by the
combined productivity level , reducing the state space by two continuous
dimensions. Dividing (21) by
and substituting normalized variables, the
reduced problem is:
The equilibrium of the HA-DSGE model is characterized by a (normalized)
consumption function and an aggregate saving rule
such that when
all households believe
, the solution to their individual problem (22) is
; and
when all agents act according to
, the best log-linear fit of
on
(conditional
on
) is
. The model is solved using a method similar to Krusell and
Smith [1998].30
The treatment of sticky beliefs in the HA-DSGE model is the natural extension
of what we did in the SOE model presented in section 4.2.2: Because the level of
now affects future wages and interest rates, a consumer’s perceptions of
that variable
now matter. Households in the DSGE model
choose their level of consumption using their perception of their normalized state
variables:
![]() |
Households who misperceive the aggregate productivity state will incorrectly predict aggregate saving at the end of the period, and thus aggregate capital and the distribution of factor prices next period.31
Because households who misperceive the aggregate productivity state will
make (slightly) different consumption–saving decisions than they would have if
fully informed, aggregate saving behavior will be different under sticky than
under frictionless expectations. Consequently, the equilibrium aggregate saving
rule will be slightly different under sticky vs frictionless expectations. When
the HA-DSGE model is solved under sticky expectations, we implicitly assume
that all households understand that all other households also have sticky
expectations, and the equilibrium aggregate saving rule is the one that emerges
from this belief structure.
To calculate the quantitative consequences of sticky expectations, we must calibrate model parameters to match the received wisdom of the literature about empirical magnitudes. We begin by calibrating market-level and preference parameters by standard methods, then specify additional parameters to characterize the idiosyncratic income shock distribution.
We assume a coefficient of relative risk aversion of , in the middle of the range
usually considered plausible. The quarterly depreciation rate
is calibrated by
assuming annual depreciation of 6%, i.e.,
. Capital’s share in
aggregate output takes its usual value of
.
We calibrate our aggregate income process as follows. We set the variances of the quarterly transitory and permanent shocks at the approximate values respectively:
To finish the calibration, we consider a simple perfect foresight model
(PF-DSGE), with all aggregate and idiosyncratic shocks turned off. We set the
perfect foresight steady state aggregate capital-to-output ratio to 12 on a
quarterly basis (corresponding to the usual ratio of 3 for capital divided by
annual income). Along with the calibrated values of and
, this choice
implies values for the other steady-state characteristics of the PF-DSGE
model:33
A perfect foresight representative agent would achieve this steady state if his
discount factor satisfied . For the HA-DSGE model, we thus set the
discount factor to
, roughly matching the target capital-to-output
ratio.34
For the SOE model we choose a much lower value of
(
). This
results in agents with wealth holdings around the median observed in the
data.35
The two values of
are chosen to span the rather wide range of calibrations
found in the micro and macro literatures. Further alternative calibrations are
possible, but experimentation has indicated that results are not sensitive to such
choices.
The annual-rate idiosyncratic transitory and permanent shocks are assumed to be
These figures are conservative in comparison with standard raw estimates from the
micro data;36
using data from the Panel Study of Income Dynamics, for example, Carroll and
Samwick [1997] estimate and
; Storesletten, Telmer,
and Yaron (2004) estimate
, with varying estimates of the
transitory component. But recent work by Low et al. [2010] suggests that
controlling for job mobility and participation decisions reduces estimates of the
permanent variance somewhat; and using very well-measured Danish
administrative data, Nielsen and Vissing-Jorgensen [2006] estimate
and
, which presumably constitute lower bounds for plausible values
for the truth in the U.S. (given the comparative generosity of the Danish welfare
state).
Since the variance of the annual permanent innovation is four times the
variance of the quarterly innovation, this calibration implies that the variance of
the idiosyncratic permanent innovations at the quarterly frequency is about 100
times the variance of the aggregate permanent innovations (0.00004 divided
by
). This is a point worth emphasizing: Idiosyncratic uncertainty is
approximately two orders of magnitude larger than aggregate uncertainty. While
reasonable people could differ a bit from our calibration of either the aggregate
or the idiosyncratic risk, no plausible calibration of either magnitude will
change the fundamental point that the aggregate component of risk is tiny
compared to the idiosyncratic component. This is why assuming that
people do not pay close attention to the macroeconomic environment is
plausible.37
We assume that the probability of unemployment is 5 percent per quarter. This approximates the historical mean unemployment rate in the U.S., but model unemployment differs from real unemployment in (at least) two important ways. First, the model does not incorporate unemployment insurance, so labor income of the unemployed is zero. Second, model unemployment shocks last only one quarter, so their duration is shorter than the typical U.S. unemployment spell (about 6 months). The idea of the calibration is that a single quarter of unemployment with zero benefits is roughly as bad as two quarters of unemployment with an unemployment insurance payment of half of permanent labor income (a reasonable approximation to the typical situation facing unemployed workers). The model could be modified to permit a more realistic treatment of unemployment spells; this is a promising topic for future research, but would involve a considerable increase in model complexity because realism would require adding the individual’s employment situation as a state variable.
The probability of mortality is set at 0.005 which implies an
expected working life of 50 years; results are not sensitive to plausible
alternative values of this parameter, so long as the life length is short
enough to permit a stationary distribution of idiosyncratic permanent
income.
We calibrate the probability of updating at 0.25 per quarter, for
several reasons. First, this is the parameter value assumed for the speed of
expectations updating by Mankiw and Reis [2002] in their analysis of the
consequences of sticky expectations for inflation. They argue that an average
frequency of updating of once a year is intuitively plausible. Second,
Carroll [2003] estimates an empirical process for the adjustment process
for household inflation expectations in which the point estimate of the
corresponding parameter is 0.27 for inflation expectations and 0.32 for
unemployment expectations; the similarity of these figures suggests 0.25 is a
reasonable benchmark, and provides some insulation against the charge
that the model is ad hoc: It is calibrated in a way that corresponds to
estimates of the stickiness of expectations in a fundamentally different
context. Finally, empirical results presented below will also suggest a
speed of updating for U.S. consumption dynamics of about 0.25 per
quarter.
This section briefly characterizes some of the equilibrium characteristics of the solutions to the models under the parameters specified above. Results are reported in Table 2.
Note first the considerable difference between the mean level of assets in the HA-DSGE and SOE models (first row of the table). As indicated above, this reflects our goal of presenting results that span the full range of calibrations in the micro and macro literatures; the micro literature has often focused on trying to explain the wealth holdings of the median household, which are much smaller than average wealth holdings.
The table suggests a broad generalization that we have confirmed with extensive experimentation: With respect to either cross section statistics, mean outcomes, or idiosyncratic consumption dynamics, the frictionless expectations and sticky expectations models are virtually indistinguishable using microeconomic data, and very similar in most aggregate implications aside from the dynamics of aggregate consumption.
The calibrated models can now be used to evaluate the effects of sticky expectations on consumption dynamics. We begin this section with an empirical benchmark on U.S. data that will guide our investigation of the implications of the model. We then demonstrate that simulated data from the sticky expectations models quantitatively and qualitatively reproduces the key patterns of aggregate and idiosyncratic consumption data.
The random walk model provides the framework around which both micro and
macro consumption literatures have been organized. Reinterpreted to incorporate
CRRA utility and permit time-varying interest rates, the random walk
proposition has frequently been formulated as a claim that in regressions
of the form:
For macroeconomic models (including the HA-DSGE setup in Section 4.3),
simulation analysis shows that the relationship between the normalized asset
stock and the expected interest rate
is nearly linear, so (23) can
be reformulated with no loss of statistical power as
Campbell and Mankiw [1989] famously proposed a modification of this model
in which a proportion of income goes to rule-of-thumb consumers who
spend
in every period. They argued that
can be estimated
by incorporating the predictable component of income growth as an
additional regressor. Finally, Dynan [2000] and Sommer [2007] show
that in some habit formation models, the size of the habit formation
parameter can be captured by including lagged consumption growth as a
regressor. These considerations lead to a benchmark specification of the form:
There is an extensive existing literature on aggregate consumption dynamics, but Sommer [2007] is the only paper we are aware of that estimates an equation of precisely this form in aggregate data. Sommer [2007] interprets the serial correlation of consumption growth as reflecting habit formation.38 However, Sommer’s choice of instruments, estimation methodology, and tests do not correspond precisely to our purposes here, so we have produced our own estimates using U.S. data.
In Table 3 we conduct a simple empirical exercise along the lines of Sommer’s work, modified to correspond to the testable implications of our model for aggregate U.S. data.39 Three points are worth emphasizing here.
First, while the existing empirical literature has tended to focus on spending on nondurables and services, there are reasons to be skeptical about the measurement of quarterly dynamics (or lack of such dynamics) in large portions of the services component of measured spending.40 Hence, we report results both for the traditional measure of nondurables and services spending, and for the more restricted category of nondurables spending alone. Fortunately, as the table shows, our results are robust to the measure of spending. Indeed, similar results hold even when the measure of spending is the broader measure of total personal consumption expenditures, or for an even stricter version of nondurables spending.
Second, Sommer [2007] emphasizes the importance of taking account of the effects of measurement error and transitory shocks on high frequency consumption data. In principle, measurement error in the level of consumption could lead to a severe downward bias in the estimated serial correlation of measured consumption growth as distinct from ‘true’ consumption growth. The simplest solution to this problem is the classic response to measurement error in any explanatory variable: Instrumental variables estimation. This point is illustrated in the fact that instrumenting drastically increases the estimated serial correlation of consumption growth.
Finally, we needed to balance the desire for the empirical exercise to match the theory with the need for sufficiently powerful instruments. This would not be a problem if, in empirical work, we could use once-lagged instruments as is possible for the theoretical model. However, empirical consumption data are subject to time aggregation bias (Working [1960], Campbell and Mankiw [1989]), which can be remedied by lagging the time-aggregated instruments an extra period. To increase the predictive power of the lagged instruments, we augmented with two variables traditionally known to have predictive power: The Federal Funds rate and the expectations component of the University of Michigan’s Index of Consumer Sentiment (cf. Carroll et al. [1994]).41
The table demonstrates three main points. First, when lagged consumption growth is excluded from the regression equation, the classic Campbell and Mankiw [1989] result holds: Consumption growth is strongly related to predictable income growth. Second, when predictable income growth is excluded but lagged consumption growth is included, the serial correlation of consumption growth is estimated to be in the range of 0.7–0.8, consistent with Havranek et al. [2017] survey of the ‘habits’ literature and very far from the benchmark random walk coefficient of zero. Finally, in the ‘horse race’ regression that pits predictable income growth against lagged consumption growth, lagged consumption growth retains its statistical significance and large point estimate, while the predictable income growth term becomes statistically insignificant (and economically small).
None of these points is a peculiarity of the U.S. data. Carroll et al. [2011] performed similar exercises for all eleven countries for which they could obtain the required data, and robustly obtained similar results across almost all of those countries.
Havranek et al. [2017]’s meta-analysis of the micro literature is consistent with
Dynan [2000]’s early finding that there is little evidence of serial correlation in
household-level consumption growth. Such a lack of serial correlation is a direct
implication of the canonical Hall [1978] certainty-equivalent model with
quadratic utility. But in principle, even without habits, a more modern model
like ours with precautionary saving motives predicts that there will be some
positive serial correlation in consumption growth. To see why, think of the
behavior of a household whose wealth, leading up to date , was near its target
value (for a proof that such a target value will exist in models of the class we are
using, see Carroll [2016]). Now in period
this household experiences a large
negative transitory shock to income, pushing buffer stock wealth far
below its target. The model says the household will cut back sharply
on consumption to rebuild its buffer stock, and during that period of
rebuilding the expected growth rate of consumption will be persistently
above its long-term rate (but declining asymptotically toward that rate).
That is, in a univariate analysis, consumption growth will exhibit serial
correlation.
But as the foregoing discussion suggests, the model says there is a much more
direct indicator than lagged consumption growth for current consumption
growth: The lagged value of , the buffer stock of assets.
The same fundamental point holds for a model in which there is an explicit liquidity constraint (our model has no such constraint, but the precautionary motive induces something that looks like a ‘soft’ liquidity constraint). Zeldes [1989a] pointed out long ago that the Euler equation on which the random walk proposition is based fails to hold for consumers who are liquidity constrained; if consumers with low levels of wealth (relative to their permanent income) are more likely to be constrained, then low wealth consumers will experience systematically faster consumption growth than otherwise-similar high-wealth consumers. Zeldes found empirical evidence of such a pattern, as has a large subsequent literature.
It is less clear is whether models in this class imply that any residual serial correlation will remain once the lagged level of assets has been controlled for. In numerical models like ours, such quantitative questions can be answered only by numerically solving and simulating the model, which is what we do here.
The model predicts that the relationship between and
will be nonlinear and downward sloping, but theory does not imply
any specific functional form. We experimented with a number of ways
of capturing the role of
but will spare the reader the unedifying
discussion of those experiments because they all reached conclusions similar
to those of a particularly simple case, inspired by the original analysis
of Zeldes [1989a]: We simply include a dummy variable that indicates
whether last period’s
is low. Specifically, we define
as 0 if
household
’s level of
in period
is in the bottom 1 percent of the
distribution, and
otherwise. (We could have chosen, say, 10 or 20
percent with qualitatively similar, though less quantitatively impressive,
results).
So, in data simulated from our SOE model, we estimate regressions of the form:42
Results for the frictionless model are presented the upper panel of Table 4.43 For our purposes, the most important conclusion is that the predictable component of idiosyncratic consumption growth is very modest. In the version of the model that corresponds to the thought experiment above, in which consumption growth should have some positive serial correlation, the magnitude of that correlation is only 0.019.44
The second row of the table presents the results of a Campbell and
Mankiw [1989]-type exercise regressing . From
our definitions above,
The existing micro literature has typically found much larger Campbell–Mankiw
coefficients than ours. However, much of that literature has made little effort to
determine the extent to which the predictable component of income growth
reflects permanent underlying growth rates like versus the extent to which
that predictability comes from purely transitory movements. If we were to use
instruments that had no power for the transitory component but did have
power for
, our estimated
coefficient would be close to 1 (because
consumption growth in models of this kind settles down in the long run to
something close to the underlying growth rate of permanent income).
Thus, our view is that little can be learned from the magnitude of the
coefficient.
The third row confirms the proposition articulated above: For people with very low levels of wealth, the model implies rapid consumption growth as they dig themselves out of their hole.
The final row presents the results when all three terms are present. Interestingly, the coefficient on lagged consumption growth actually increases, to about 0.06, when we control for the other two terms. But this is still easily in the range of estimates from 0.0 to 0.1 that Havranek et al. [2017] indicate characterizes the micro literature.
The final point to note from the frictionless model is the very small values of
the ’s. Even the version of the model including all three explanatory
variables can explain only about 2 percent of the variation in consumption
growth.
The table’s lower panel contains results from estimating the same regressions
on the sticky expectations version of the model. These results are virtually
indistinguishable from those obtained for the frictionless expectations model. As
before, aside from the precautionary component captured by , idiosyncratic
consumption growth is largely unpredictable.
Table 3 presents the results that an econometrician would obtain from estimating an equation like (24) using aggregate data generated by the same models whose micro results are presented in Table 4. In short, it shows that even though simulated households with sticky expectations do not exhibit any meaningful predictability of idiosyncratic consumption growth, aggregate consumption growth in an economy populated by such consumers exhibits a high degree of serial correlation (similar to that in empirical data).
To generate these results, we simulate the small open economy model for 200 quarters, tracking aggregate dynamics to generate a dataset whose size is similar to the 57 years of NIPA data used for Table 3. Because there is some variation in coefficient estimates depending on the random number generator’s seed, we repeat the simulation exercise 100 times. Table 5 reports average point estimates and standard errors across those 100 samples.
Given the relatively long time frame of each sample, and that the idiosyncratic shocks to income are washed away by the law of large numbers, it is feasible to use instrumental variables techniques to obtain the coefficient on the expected growth term. This is the appropriate procedure for comparison with empirical results in any case, since instrumental variables estimation is the standard way of estimating the benchmark Campbell–Mankiw model. As instruments, we use lags of consumption growth, income growth, the wealth–permanent income ratio, and income growth over a two-year span.45
Finally, for comparison to empirical results, we take into account Sommer [2007]’s
argument (based on Wilcox [1992]) that transitory components of aggregate
spending46
(hurricanes, etc) and high-frequency measurement problems introduce transitory
components in measured NIPA consumption expenditure data. Sommer
finds that measurement error produces a severe downward bias in the
empirical estimate of the serial correlation in consumption growth, relative
to the ‘true’ serial correlation coefficient. To make the simulated data
comparable to the measurement-error-distorted empirical data, we multiply our
model’s simulated aggregate spending data by a white noise error :
The top panel of Table 5 estimates (24) on simulated data for the
frictionless economy. The second and third rows indicate that consumption
growth is moderately predictable by (instrumented versions of) both
its own lag and expected income growth, of comparable magnitude to
the empirical benchmark. However, the ‘horse race’ regression in the
bottom row reveals that neither variable is significantly predictive of
consumption growth when both are present as regressors – contrary to the
robust empirical results from the U.S. and other countries (cf Carroll
et al. [2011]). The problem is that for both consumption growth and income
growth, most of the predictive power of the instruments stems from
the serial correlation of productivity growth in the model, so the
instrumented versions of the variables are highly correlated with each
other. Thus neither has distinct statistical power when they are both
included.
In the sticky expectations specification (the lower panel of the table), the
second-stage ’s are all much higher than in the frictionless model, and more
in keeping with the corresponding statistics in NIPA data. This is because high
frequency aggregate consumption growth is being driven by the predictable
sticky expectations dynamics. The first two rows show that when we
introduce measurement error as described above, the OLS estimate is
biased downward significantly. As suggested by the analysis of our ‘toy
model’ above, the IV estimate of
in the second row is close to the
figure that measures the proportion of consumers who do
not adjust their expectations in any given period; thus the intuition
derived from the toy model survives all the subsequent complications and
elaborations. The third row reflects what would have been found by Campbell
and Mankiw had they estimated their model on data produced by the
simulated ‘sticky expectations’ economy: The coefficient on predictable
component of perceived income growth term is large and highly statistically
significant.
The last row of the table presents the ‘horse race’ between the
Campbell–Mankiw model and the sticky expectations model, and shows that the
dynamics of consumption are dominated by the serial correlation in the
predictable component of consumption growth stemming from the stickiness
of expectations. This can be seen not only from the magnitude of the
coefficients, but also by comparison of the second-stage ’s, which indicate
that the contribution of predictable income growth to the predictability
of consumption growth is negligible, increasing the
from 0.261 to
0.263.
Table 6 reports the results of estimating regression (24) on data generated from the HA-DSGE model of Section 4.3; results are substantially the same as the previous analysis for the SOE model.47
The model with frictionless expectations (top panel) implies aggregate
consumption growth that is moderately (but not statistically significantly)
serially correlated when examined in isolation (second row), but the effect
“washes out” when expected income growth and the aggregate wealth to income
ratio are included in the horse race regression (fourth row). As expected in
a closed economy model, the aggregate wealth-to-income ratio is
negatively correlated with consumption growth, but its predictive power
is so slight that it is statistically insignificant in samples of only 200
quarters.
The model with sticky expectations (bottom panel) again implies a serial correlation coefficient of consumption growth not far from 0.75 in the univariate IV regression (second row). As in the SOE simulation, the horserace regression (fifth row) indicates that the apparent success of the Campbell–Mankiw specification (third row) reflects the correlation of predicted current income growth with instrumented lagged consumption growth.
To this point, we have taken to be exogenous (though reasonably
calibrated), but the probability of updating could depend at least
partly on costs and benefits, as in ‘rational’ inattention models. In this
section, we briefly examine the tradeoffs by imagining that newborns
make a once-and-for-all choice of their idiosyncratic value of
,
yielding an intuitive approximating formula for the optimal updating
frequency.48
We then conduct a numerical exercise to compute the cost of stickiness
for the calibrated models. The utility costs of having
equal to our
calibrated value of
, rather than updating every period, are on the
order of one two-thousandth of lifetime consumption, so that even small
informational costs would justify updating aggregate information only
occasionally.
In the first period of life, we assume that the consumer is employed and
experiences no transitory shocks, so that market resources are nonstochastically
equal to ; value can therefore be written as
. There is no analytical
expression for
; but, fixing all parameters aside from the variance of the
permanent aggregate shock, theoretical considerations suggest (and numerical
experiments confirm) that the consequences of permanent uncertainty for value
can be well approximated by:
Suppose now (again confirmed numerically—see Figure 2 below) that the effect of sticky expectations is approximately to reduce value by an amount proportional to the inverse of the updating probability:
This assumption has appropriate scaling properties in three senses:
Now imagine that newborns make a once-and-for-all choice of the value of ; a
higher
(faster updating) is assumed to have a linear cost
in units of normalized
value.49
The newborn’s objective is therefore to choose the
that solves:
Thus, the speed of updating should be related directly to the utility cost of
permanent uncertainty , inversely to the cost of information (cheaper
information induces faster updating), and linearly to the standard deviation of
permanent aggregate shocks.
Our calibrated models can be used to numerically calculate the welfare loss
from our specification of sticky expectations as an agent’s willingness
to pay at birth in order to avoid having for his entire
lifetime.50
Specifically, we calculate the percentage loss of permanent income that would make a
newborn indifferent between being frictionless while taking the loss versus having sticky
expectations.51
Using notation from the theoretical exercise above, define a newborn’s average lifetime (normalized) value at birth under frictionless and sticky expectations as respectively:
![]() |
where the expectation is taken over the distribution of state variables other than
that an agent might be born into (as well as the wage rate, in the
HA-DSGE model). We compute these quantities by averaging the discounted
sum of consumption utilities experienced by households over their simulated
lifetimes. A newborn’s willingness to pay (as a fraction of permanent
income) to avoid having sticky expectations can then be calculated as:
The bottom row of Table 2 reports the cost of stickiness for the SOE and HA-DSGE models. A newborn in either model is willing to give up about 0.05 percent of his permanent income to remain frictionless. These values are comparable to the findings of Maćkowiak and Wiederholt [2015], who construct a model in which, as in Reis [2006a], agents optimally choose how much attention to pay to economic shocks by weighing off costs and benefits. They find (p. 1519) that the cost of suboptimal tracking of aggregate shocks is 0.06 percent of steady state consumption.
Now that we have explained how to compute the cost of stickiness numerically,
we can test our supposition in equation (28) that the cost of stickiness might
have a roughly inverse linear relationship to . Figure 2 plots numerically
computed
for various values of
and is close to linear, as we
speculated.
Now that our calibrations and results have been presented, we are in position to make some quantitative comparisons of our model to two principal alternatives to habit formation (or our model) for explaining excess smoothness in consumption growth.
The longest-standing rival to habit formation as an explanation of consumption sluggishness is what we will call the Muth–Lucas–Pischke (henceforth, MLP) framework. The idea is not that agents are inattentive, but instead that they have imperfect information on which they (perfectly attentively) perform an optimal signal extraction problem.
Muth [1960]’s agents could observe only the level of their income, but not the split between its permanent and transitory components. He derived the optimal (mean-squared-error-minimizing) method for estimating the level of permanent income from the observed signal about the level of actual income. Lucas [1973] applied the same mathematical toolkit to solve a model in which firms are assumed to be unable to distinguish idiosyncratic from aggregate shocks. Pischke [1995] combines the ideas of Muth and Lucas and applies the result to the analysis of micro data: His consumers have no ability at all to perceive whether income shocks that hit them are aggregate or idiosyncratic, transitory or permanent. They see only their income, and do signal extraction on it.
Pischke calibrates his model with micro data in which he calculates that transitory shocks vastly outweigh permanent shocks.52 So, when a shock arrives, consumers always interpret it as being almost entirely transitory and change their consumption by little. However, macroeconometricians have long known that aggregate income shocks are close to permanent. When an aggregate permanent shock comes along, Pischkian consumers spend very little of it, confounding the aggregate permanent shock’s effect on their income with the mainly transitory idiosyncratic shocks that account for most of the total variation in their income. This misperception causes sluggishness in aggregate consumption dynamics in response to aggregate shocks. (See below for a more precise formulation of this point).
In its assumption that consumers fail to perceive aggregate shocks immediately and fully, Pischke’s model resembles ours. However, few papers in the literature after Pischke [1995] have adopted his assumption that households have no idea, when an idiosyncratic income shock occurs, whether it is transitory or permanent. Especially in the last decade or so, the literature instead has almost always assumed that consumers can perfectly perceive the transitory and permanent components of their income.53
Granting our choice to assume that consumers correctly perceive the events that are idiosyncratic to them (job changes, lottery winnings, etc), there is still a potential role for application of the MLP framework: Instead of assuming sticky expectations, we could instead have assumed that consumers perform a signal extraction exercise on only the aggregate component of their income, because they cannot perceive the transitory/permanent split for the (tiny) part of their income change that reflects aggregate macroeconomic developments.
In principle (and more plausibly than under Pischke’s assumption of complete ignorance), such confusion could generate excess smoothness. To see how, note that in the Muth framework, agents update their estimate of permanent income according to an equation of the form:54
We can now consider the dynamics of aggregate consumption in response to
the arrival of an aggregate shock that (unbeknownst to the consumer) is a
permanent shock. The consumer spends of the shock in the first period,
leaving
unspent because that reflects the average transitory
component of an undifferentiated shock. However, since the shock really was
permanent, income next period does not fall back as the consumer guessed it
would on the basis of the mistaken belief that
of the shock was
transitory. The next-period consumer treats this surprise as a positive shock
relative to expected income, and spends the same proportion
out
of the perceived new shock. These dynamics continue indefinitely, but
with each successive perceived shock (and therefore each consumption
increment) being smaller than the last by the proportion
. Thus,
after a true permanent shock received in period
, the full-information
prediction of the expected dynamics of future consumption changes would be
.55
At first blush, this predictability in consumption growth would appear to be a violation of Hall [1978]’s proof that, for consumers who make rational estimates of their permanent income, consumption must be a random walk. The reconciliation is that what Hall proves is that consumption must be a random walk with respect to the knowledge the consumer has. The random walk proposition remains true for consumers whose knowledge base contains only the perceived level of aggregate income. Our thought experiment was to ask how much predictability would be found by an econometrician who knows more than the consumer about the level of aggregate permanent income.
The in-principle reconciliation of econometric evidence of predictability/excess smoothness in consumption growth, and the random walk proposition, is therefore that the econometricians who are making their forecasts of aggregate consumption growth use other variables in addition to the lagged history of aggregate income itself (and that those variables have useful predictive power).56
We now turn to the question of whether the Muth–Lucas–Pischke
story is a good quantitative explanation of the size of aggregate excess
smoothness. Appendix C.4 shows that, defining the signal-to-noise ratio
, Muth’s derivations imply that the optimal updating coefficient
is:57
Plugging our calibrations of and
from section 5 into (??), the
model yields a predicted value of
—very far below the
approximately
estimate from Havranek et al. [2017] and even farther
below our estimate of roughly
–
for U.S. data. This reflects the
well-known fact that aggregate income is hard to distinguish from a
random walk; if it were perceived to be a perfect random walk with no
transitory component at all, the serial correlation in its growth would be
zero.58
Considerations similar to the foregoing apply, at least to some degree, to the Reis [2006a] model. Moreover, that model has a further disadvantage relative to any of the other three stories (habits, MLP, or our model). In Reis’s model consumers update their information on a regular schedule; under a plausible calibration of the model, once a year. One implication of the model is that the change in consumption at the next reset is unpredictable; this implies that aggregate consumption growth would be unpredictable at any horizon beyond, say, the one-year horizon. But, the habit formation assumption was incorporated into macroeconomic models in large part to explain the fact that consumption growth is forecastable over extended periods—well beyond the one year horizon. A calibration of the Reis model in which consumers update once a year therefore leaves much of the original puzzle in place.59
Using a traditional utility function that does not incorporate habits, the literature on the microfoundations of consumption behavior has made great strides over the past couple of decades in constructing models that are faithful to many of the microeconomic facts about consumption, income dynamics, and the distribution of wealth. But over roughly the same interval, habit formation has gone from an exotic hypothesis to a standard assumption in the representative agent macroeconomics literature, because habits allow representative agent models to match the measured smoothness in aggregate consumption growth. This conflict, thrown into sharp focus by the recent meta-analysis of both literatures by Havranek et al. [2017], is arguably the most important puzzle in the microfoundations of macroeconomic consumption behavior.
Our argument is that this conflict can be resolved by applying insights from the literature on ‘inattention’ that has developed robustly since the early contributions of Sims [2003], Woodford [2002], Mankiw and Reis [2002], and others. In the presence of such inattention, aggregation of the behavior of microeconomic consumers without habits generates aggregate consumption dynamics that match the ‘excess smoothness’ facts that have induced the representative agent literature to embrace habits.
The sticky expectations assumption is more attractive for modeling consumption than for other areas where it has been more widely applied, because in the consumption context there is a well-defined utility-based metric for calculating the cost of sticky expectations (in contrast, say, with models in which households’ inflation expectations are sticky; the cost of misperceiving the inflation rate is unclear). The cost to consumers of our proposed degree of macroeconomic inattention is quite modest, for reasons that will be familiar to anyone who has worked with both micro and macro data: Idiosyncratic variation is vastly greater than aggregate variation. This means that the small imperfections in macroeconomic perceptions proposed here have very modest utility consequences. So long as consumers respond appropriately to their idiosyncratic shocks (which we assume they do), the failure to keep completely up-to-date with aggregate developments simply does not matter much.
While some previous papers have mooted the idea that inattention (or imperfect information) might generate excess smoothness, the modeling question is a quantitative one (‘how much excess smoothness can a sensible model explain?’). We argue that the imperfect information models and mechanisms proposed in the prior literature are quantitatively unable simultaneously to match the micro and macro quantitative facts, while our model matches all the main stylized facts from both literatures.
In future work, it would be interesting to enrich the model so that it has plausible implications for how the degree of attention might vary over time or across people, and to connect the model to the available expectations data (for example, measures of consumer sentiment, or measures of uncertainty constructed from news sources, cf Baker et al. [2016]). Such work might be particularly useful in any attempt to understand how behavioral dynamics change between normal times (in which news coverage of macroeconomic dynamics is not front-page material) and crisis times (in which it is).
Andrew B. Abel. Asset prices under habit formation and catching up with the joneses. American Economic Review, 80(2):38–42, May 1990.
George A. Akerlof and Janet L. Yellen. A near-rational model of the business cycle, with wage and price intertia. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 100(5):823–38, 1985.
Fernando Alvarez, Luigi Guiso, and Francesco Lippi. Durable consumption and asset management with transaction and observation costs. American Economic Review, 102(5):2272–2300, August 2012. URL https://ideas.repec.org/a/aea/aecrev/v102y2012i5p2272-2300.html.
Scott R Baker, Nicholas Bloom, and Steven J Davis. Measuring economic policy uncertainty. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 131(4):1593–1636, 2016.
Olivier J. Blanchard. Debt, deficits, and finite horizons. Journal of Political Economy, 93 (2):223–247, April 1985.
Michele Boldrin, Lawrence J. Christiano, and Jonas D. Fisher. Habit persistence, asset returns and the business cycle. American Economic Review, 91(1):149–66, 2001.
Martin Browning and M. Dolores Collado. The response of expenditures to anticipated income changes: Panel data estimates. American Economic Review, 91(3):681–692, 2001.
Martin Browning and Thomas F. Crossley. The life-cycle model of consumption and savings. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 15(3):3–22, 2001.
Guillermo A. Calvo. Staggered contracts in a utility-maximizing framework. Journal of Monetary Economics, 12(3):383–98, 1983.
John Campbell and Angus Deaton. Why is Consumption So Smooth? The Review of Economic Studies, 56(3):357–373, jul 1989. ISSN 0034-6527. URL http://www.jstor.org/stable/2297552. http://www.jstor.org/stable/2297552.
John Y. Campbell and N. Gregory Mankiw. Consumption, income, and interest rates: Reinterpreting the time-series evidence. In Olivier J. Blanchard and Stanley Fischer, editors, NBER Macroeconomics Annual, 1989, pages 185–216. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, 1989. URL http://www.nber.org/papers/w2924.pdf. http://www.nber.org/papers/w2924.pdf.
Christopher D. Carroll. Macroeconomic Expectations of Households and Professional Forecasters. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 118 (1):269–298, 2003. URL http://www.econ2.jhu.edu/people/ccarroll/epidemiologyQJE.pdf. http://www.econ2.jhu.edu/people/ccarroll/epidemiologyQJE.pdf.
Christopher D. Carroll. Theoretical foundations of buffer stock saving. manuscript, Department of Economics, Johns Hopkins University, 2016. URL http://www.econ2.jhu.edu/people/ccarroll/papers/BufferStockTheory.pdf. Available at http://www.econ2.jhu.edu/people/ccarroll/papers/BufferStockTheory.
Christopher D. Carroll and Miles S. Kimball. On the Concavity of the Consumption Function. Econometrica, 64(4):981–992, 1996. URL http://www.econ2.jhu.edu/people/ccarroll/concavity.pdf. http://www.econ2.jhu.edu/people/ccarroll/concavity.pdf.
Christopher D. Carroll and Andrew A. Samwick. The Nature of Precautionary Wealth. Journal of Monetary Economics, 40(1):41–71, 1997. URL http://www.econ2.jhu.edu/people/ccarroll/papers/nature.pdf.
Christopher D. Carroll, Jeffrey C. Fuhrer, and David W. Wilcox. Does consumer sentiment forecast household spending? If so, why? American Economic Review, 84(5):1397–1408, 1994. URL http://www.econ2.jhu.edu/people/ccarroll/SentAERCarrollFuhrerWilcox.pdf. http://www.econ2.jhu.edu/people/ccarroll/SentAERCarrollFuhrerWilcox.pdf.
Christopher D. Carroll, Martin Sommer, and Jiri Slacalek. International evidence on sticky consumption growth. Review of Economics and Statistics, 93(4):1135–1145, October 2011. doi: 10.1162/REST\_a\_00122. URL https://doi.org/10.1162/REST_a_00122. http://www.econ2.jhu.edu/people/ccarroll/papers/cssIntlStickyC/.
Christopher D Carroll, Jiri Slacalek, and Kiichi Tokuoka. Buffer-stock saving in a krusell–smith world. Economics Letters, 132:97–100, 2015. doi: doi:10.1016/j.econlet.2015.04.021. URL http://www.econ2.jhu.edu/people/ccarroll/papers/cstKS/. At http://www.econ2.jhu.edu/people/ccarroll/papers/cstKS/; extended version available as ECB Working Paper number 1633, https://www.ecb.europa.eu/pub/pdf/scpwps/ecbwp1633.pdf.
Christopher D. Carroll, Jiri Slacalek, Kiichi Tokuoka, and Matthew N. White. The distribution of wealth and the marginal propensity to consume. Quantitative Economics, 8:977–1020, 2017. doi: 10.3982/QE694. URL http://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/10.3982/QE694/pdf. At http://www.econ2.jhu.edu/people/ccarroll/papers/cstwMPC.
V. V. Chari, Patrick J. Kehoe, and Ellen R. McGrattan. A critique of structural vars using real business cycle theory. working paper 631, Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis, 2005.
Raj Chetty and Adam Szeidl. Consumption commitments and habit formation. Econometrica, 84:855–890, 03 2016. URL https://ideas.repec.org/a/wly/emetrp/v84y2016ip855-890.html.
Laurence J. Christiano, Martin Eichenbaum, and Charles L. Evans. Nominal rigidities and the dynamic effects of a shock to monetary policy. Journal of Political Economy, 113(1): 1–45, February 2005.
John H. Cochrane. The sensitivity of tests of the intertemporal allocation of consumption to near-rational alternatives. American Economic Review, 79:319–37, 1991.
Olivier Coibion and Yuriy Gorodnichenko. Information Rigidity and the Expectations Formation Process: A Simple Framework and New Facts. American Economic Review, 105 (8):2644–2678, August 2015.
George M. Constantinides. Habit formation: A resolution of the equity premium puzzle. Journal of Political Economy, 98(3):519–543, June 1990.
Angus S. Deaton. Understanding Consumption. Oxford University Press, New York, 1992.
Karen E. Dynan. Habit formation in consumer preferences: Evidence from panel data. American Economic Review, 90(3), 2000. URL http://www.jstor.org/stable/117335. http://www.jstor.org/stable/117335.
Rochelle M Edge, Thomas Laubach, and John C Williams. Learning and shifts in long-run productivity growth. Journal of Monetary Economics, 54(8):2421–2438, 2007.
Andreas Fagereng, Martin B. Holm, and Gisle J. Natvik. Mpc heterogeneity and household balance sheets. discussion paper, Statistics Norway, 2017.
John G. Fernald, Robert Hall, James Stock, and Mark Watson. The disappointing recovery of output after 2009. Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, Spring, 2017.
Milton A. Friedman. A Theory of the Consumption Function. Princeton University Press, 1957.
Jeffrey C. Fuhrer. Habit formation in consumption and its implications for monetary policy models. American Economic Review, 90(3):367–390, June 2000. URL http://www.jstor.org/stable/117334. http://www.jstor.org/stable/117334.
Jeffrey C. Fuhrer. Intrinsic persistence in expectations: Evidence from micro data. Presentation at NBER Summer Institute, Federal Reserve Bank of Boston, 2017a.
Jeffrey C. Fuhrer. Expectations as a source of macroeconomic persistence: Evidence from survey expectations in a dynamic macro model. Journal of Monetary Economics, 86:22–55, April 2017b.
Xavier Gabaix. A sparsity-based model of bounded rationality. The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 129(4):1661–1710, 2014. URL https://ideas.repec.org/a/oup/qjecon/v129y2014i4p1661-1710.html.
Joseph W. Gruber. A present value test of habits and the current account. Journal of Monetary Economics, 51(7):1495–1507, 2004.
Robert E. Hall. Stochastic implications of the life-cycle/permanent income hypothesis: Theory and evidence. Journal of Political Economy, 96: 971–87, 1978. URL http://www.stanford.edu/~rehall/Stochastic-JPE-Dec-1978.pdf. Available at http://www.stanford.edu/~rehall/Stochastic-JPE-Dec-1978.pdf.
Tomas Havranek, Marek Rusnak, and Anna Sokolova. Habit formation in consumption: A meta-analysis. European Economic Review, 95:142–167, 2017. doi: 10.1016/j.euroecorev.2017.03.009. URL https://doi.org/10.1016/j.euroecorev.2017.03.009.
Urban J. Jermann. Asset pricing in production economies. Journal of Monetary Economics, 42(2):257–75, April 1998.
David S. Johnson, Jonathan A. Parker, and Nicholas S. Souleles. Household expenditure and the income tax rebates of 2001. American Economic Review, 96(5):1589–1610, December 2006. URL http://ideas.repec.org/a/aea/aecrev/v96y2006i5p1589-1610.html.
Dale W. Jorgenson, Mun S. Ho, and Kevin J. Stiroh. A retrospective look at the u.s. productivity growth resurgence. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 22(1):3–24, Winter 2008.
Fatih Karahan, Sean Mihaljevich, and Laura Pilossoph. Understanding permanent and temporary income shocks. URL link retrieved on 03/02/2018 here., 2017.
Per Krusell and Anthony A. Smith. Income and wealth heterogeneity in the macroeconomy. Journal of Political Economy, 106(5):867–896, 1998.
Lorenz Kueng. Explaining consumption excess sensitivity with near-rationality: Evidence from large predetermined payments. working paper 21772, National Bureau of Economic Research, December 2015.
Hamish Low, Costas Meghir, and Luigi Pistaferri. Wage risk and employment over the life cycle. American Economic Review, 100(4):1432–1467, 2010.
Robert E. Lucas. Some international evidence on output-inflation tradeoffs. American Economic Review, 63:326–334, June 1973.
Bartosz Maćkowiak and Mirko Wiederholt. Business cycle dynamics under rational inattention. The Review of Economic Studies, 82(4):1502–1532, 2015. doi: 10.1093/restud/rdv027. URL +http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/restud/rdv027.
N. Gregory Mankiw and Ricardo Reis. Sticky information versus sticky prices: A proposal to replace the new keynesian phillips curve. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 117(4):1295–1328, November 2002.
Stephen Morris and Hyun Song Shin. Inertia of forward-looking expectations. The American Economic Review, 96(2):152–157, 2006. ISSN 00028282. URL http://www.jstor.org/stable/30034632.
John F. Muth. Optimal properties of exponentially weighted forecasts. Journal of the American Statistical Association, 55(290):299–306, 1960.
Helena Skyt Nielsen and Annette Vissing-Jorgensen. The impact of labor income risk on educational choices: Estimates and implied risk aversion. Manuscript, 2006.
Jörn-Steffen Pischke. Individual income, incomplete information, and aggregate consumption. Econometrica, 63(4):805–40, 1995.
Ricardo Reis. Inattentive consumers. Journal of Monetary Economics, 53(8):1761–1800, 2006a.
Ricardo Reis. Inattentive producers. Review of Economic Studies, 73(3):793–821, 2006b.
Christopher Sims. Implications of rational inattention. Journal of Monetary Economics, 50(3):665–690, 2003. available at http://ideas.repec.org/a/eee/moneco/v50y2003i3p665-690.html.
Martin Sommer. Habit formation and aggregate consumption dynamics. Advances in Macroeconomics, 7(1):Article 21, 2007.
Douglas Staiger, James H. Stock, and Mark W. Watson. Prices wages and the us nairu in the 1990s. In Alan B. Krueger and Robert Solow, editors, The Roaring Nineties: Can Full Employment Be Sustained? The Russell Sage Foundation and Century Press, New York, 2001.
Kjetil Storesletten, Chris I. Telmer, and Amir Yaron. Consumption and risk sharing over the life cycle. Journal of Monetary Economics, 51(3):609–633, Apr 2004. URL http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/B6VBW-4BWMTRW-2/1/4934de112177c84dc55a3f37dbde0e16.
Christian E. Weber. Intertemporal non-separability and ‘rule-of-thumb’ consumption. Journal of Monetary Economics, 49:293–308, 2002.
David W. Wilcox. The construction of u.s. consumption data: Some facts and their implications for empirical work. American Economic Review, 82(4):922–941, 1992.
Michael Woodford. Imperfect common knowledge and the effects of monetary policy. In P. Aghion, R. Frydman, J. Stiglitz, and M. Woodford, editors, Knowledge, Information and Expectations in Modern Macroeconomics. Princeton University Press, Princeton, 2002. URL http://EconPapers.repec.org/RePEc:nbr:nberwo:8673.
Holbrook Working. Note on the correlation of first differences of averages in a random chain. Econometrica, 28(4):916–918, 1960.
Stephen P. Zeldes. Consumption and liquidity constraints: An empirical investigation. Journal of Political Economy, 97:305–46, 1989a. URL http://www.jstor.org/stable/1831315. Available at http://www.jstor.org/stable/1831315.
Stephen P. Zeldes. Optimal consumption with stochastic income: Deviations from certainty equivalence. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 104(2):275–298, May 1989b.
This appendix presents a representative agent model for analyzing the consequences of sticky expectations in a DSGE framework while abstracting from idiosyncratic income shocks and the death (and replacement) of households. It builds upon the modeling assumptions in Section 4.1 to formulate the representative agent model, then presents simulated results analogous to Section 6. The primary advantage of this model is that it allows fast analysis of sticky expectations in a closed economy, yielding very similar results to the heterogeneous agents DSGE model with less than a minute of computation, rather than a few hours. However, the model is not truly “representative agent” under sticky expectations, as the representative household’s perception of the aggregate state is “smeared” over the state space. As presented below, the realized level of consumption represents the average level of consumption chosen by the “multiple minds” of the representative household.
The representative agent’s state variables at the time of its consumption decision are the level
of market resources , the productivity of labor
, and the growth rate of productivity
. Idiosyncratic productivity shocks
and
do not exist, and the possibility of death is
irrelevant; aggregate permanent and transitory productivity shocks
and
are
distributed as usual.
The representative agent’s problem can be written in Bellman form as:60
Normalizing the representative agent’s problem by the productivity level
as in the SOE and HA-DSGE models, the problem’s state space can be reduced
to:61
![]() | (35) |
![]() |
The representative agent model can be solved using the endogenous grid method, following the same
procedure as for the SOE model described in Appendix B.1, yielding normalized consumption function
.62
The typical interpretation of a representative agent model is that it represents a continuum of households that face no idiosyncratic shocks, and thus all find themselves with the same state variables; idiosyncratic decisions are equivalent to aggregate, representative agent decisions. Once we introduce sticky expectations of aggregate productivity, this no longer holds: different households will have different perceptions of productivity, and thus make different consumption decisions.
To handle this departure from the usual representative agent framework, we take a “multiple
minds” or quasi-representative agent approach. That is, we model the representative agent as
being made up of a continuum of households who all correctly perceive the level of aggregate
market resources , but might have different perceptions of the aggregate productivity
state. Each household chooses their level of consumption based on their perception of the
productivity state; the realized level of aggregate consumption is simply the sum across all
households.
Formally, we track the distribution of perceptions about the aggregate productivity state as
a stochastic vector over the current growth rate
, representing the fraction of
households who perceive each value of
, and a vector
representing the average
perceived productivity level among households who perceive each
. As in our other models,
agents update their perception of the true aggregate productivity state
with
probability
; likewise, the distinction between frictionless and sticky expectations is simply
whether
or
.
Defining as the
-length vector with zeros in all elements but the
-th, which has a
one, the distribution of population perceptions of growth rate
evolves according
to:
![]() | (36) |
That is, a proportion of households who perceive each growth rate update their perception
to the true state
, while the other
proportion of households maintain
their prior belief (which might already be
).
The vector of average perceptions of aggregate productivity for each growth rate can then be calculated as:
![]() | (37) |
That is, the average perception of productivity in each growth state is the weighted average of updaters and non-updaters who perceive that growth rate.63
Households who perceive each growth rate act as a partial representative agent,
choosing their level of consumption according to their perception of normalized market
resources. Defining
as perceived normalized market resources for
households who perceive the aggregate growth rate is
, aggregate consumption
is:
![]() | (38) |
This represents the weighted average of per-state consumption levels of the partial representative agents.
When the representative agent frictionlessly updates its information every period (),
equations (36) and (37) say that
and
(with irrelevant values in the other
vector elements), so that the representative agent is truly representative. When expectations are
sticky (
), the representative agent’s perceptions of the growth rate become “smeared”
across its past realizations; its perceptions the productivity level likewise deviate from the true
value, even for the part of the representative agent who perceives the true growth
rate.64
We calibrate the RA model using the same parameters as for the HA-DSGE model (see
Section 5.1 and Table 1), except that there are no idiosyncratic income shocks
() and the possibility of death is irrelevant (
). After solving the
model, we utilize the same simulation procedure described in Section 6, taking 100 samples of
200 quarters each; average coefficients and standard errors across the samples are reported in
Table 7.
The upper panel of Table 7 shows that under frictionless expectations, consumption growth in the representative agent model cannot be predicted to any statistically significant degree under any specification. The lower panel, under sticky expectations, yields results that are strikingly similar to the SOE model in Table 5. Both (instrumented) lagged consumption growth and expected income growth are significant predictors of aggregate consumption growth, but the ‘horse race’ regression reveals that the predictability is dominated by serially correlated consumption growth, confirming the results of the two heterogeneous agents models.
Consider the household’s normalized problem in the SOE model, given in (16).
Substituting the latter two constraints into the maximand, this problem has one
first order condition (with respect to ), which is sufficient to characterize the
solution:
![]() | (39) |
![]() |
We use the endogenous grid method to solve the model by iterating on the first order condition. Eliding some uninteresting complications, our procedure is straightforward:
The numerically computed consumption function can then be used to simulate a population of households, as described in Appendix B.2.
Consider the household’s normalized problem in the HA-DSGE model, given in (22). Recalling
that we are taking the aggregate saving rule as given, optimal consumption is
characterized by the solution to the first-order condition:
![]() | (40) |
![]() |
Solving the HA-DSGE model requires a nested loop procedure in the style of Krusell and
Smith [1998], as the equilibrium of the model is a fixed point in the space of household beliefs
about the aggregate saving rule. For the outer loop, searching for the equilibrium , we use
the following procedure:
The inner solution loop (step 3) proceeds very similarly to the SOE solution method above, with differences in the following steps:
This appendix describes the procedure for generating a history of simulated outcomes once the
household’s optimization problem has been solved to yield consumption function (or
in the representative agent model). We first describe the procedure for the SOE and
HA-DSGE models from the body of the text, then summarize the simulation method for the
representative agent model of Appendix A.
In any given period , there are exactly
households in the simulated
population. At the very beginning of the simulation, all households are given an initial level of
capital:
in the SOE model (as if they were newborns) and
in the
HA-DSGE model. Likewise, normalized aggregate capital is set to the perfect foresight
steady state
. At the beginning of time, all households have
and
correct perceptions of the aggregate state. We initialize
and
, average
growth.
Time begins in period , but the reported history begins at
following a
1000 period “burn in” phase to allow the population distribution of
and
to reach
its long run distribution. In each simulated period
, we execute the following
steps:
We simulate a total of about 21,000 periods, so that the final period is indexed by
. The time series values reported in Table 2 are calculated on the span of the
history,
to
; the cross sectional values in this table are averaged across all
within-period cross sections. The time series regressions in Tables 5 and 6 partition the history
into 200 samples of 100 quarters each; the tables report average coefficients and statistics
across 100 sample regressions.
When simulating the representative agent model of Appendix A, only a few changes are
necessary to the procedure above. The vectors of perceptions are initialized to and
, so the “entire” representative agent has correct perceptions of the aggregate state.
No households are ever “replaced” in the RA simulation, idiosyncratic shocks do
not exist; only aggregate market resources are relevant. The vectors of perceptions
evolve according to (36) and (37), and aggregate consumption is determined using
(38).
The microeconomic (or cross sectional) regressions in Table 4 are generated using a
single 4000 period sample of the history, from to
, using 5000 of the
20,000 households. After dropping observations with
, this leaves about 19
million observations, far larger than any consumption panel dataset that we know of.
Standard errors are thus vanishingly small, and have little meaning in any case,
which is why we do not report them in the table summarizing our microsimulation
results.
When making their forecasts of expected income growth, households are assumed to forecast
that the transitory component of income will grow by the factor , which is the forecast
implied by their observation of the idiosyncratic transitory component of income.
Substantively, this assumption reflects the real-world fact that essentially all of the predictable
variation in income growth at the household level comes from idiosyncratic components of
income.
After simulating a population of households using the procedure in Appendix B.2, we have a
history of micro observations and a history of aggregate permanent
productivity levels
. Each household index
contains the history of many agents, as
the agent at
dies and is replaced at the beginning of any period with
. Let
be
the
-th time
index where
; further define
, the number of
replacement events for household index
.
A single consumer’s (normalized) discounted sum of lifetime utility is then:
![]() | (41) |
Normalizing by aggregate productivity at birth is equivalent to normalizing
by the consumer’s total productivity at birth
because
at birth by
assumption.
The total number of households who are born and die in the history is:
![]() | (42) |
The overall expected lifetime value at birth can then be computed as:
![]() | (43) |
Because we use and
, and agents live for 200 periods on average
(
), our simulated history includes about
2 million consumer
lifetimes. The standard errors on our numerically calculated
and
are thus negligible
and not reported.
In the SOE model, we use the same random seed for the frictionless and sticky specifications, so the same sequence of replacement events and income shocks occurs in both. With no externalities or general equilibrium effects, the distribution of states that consumers are born into is likewise identical, so the “value ratio” calculation is valid.
The cost of stickiness in the HA-DSGE model is slightly more complicated. If we used the
generated histories of the frictionless and sticky specifications to compute and
, the
calculated
would represent a newborn’s willingness-to-pay for everyone to be frictionless
rather than sticky. We are interested in the utility cost of just one agent having sticky
expectations, so an alternate procedure is required.
We compute in the HA-DSGE model the same as in the SOE model. However,
is
calculated as the expected lifetime (normalized) value of a newborn who is frictionless but lives
in a world otherwise populated by sticky consumers. To do this, we simulate a new history of
micro observations using the consumption function for the sticky HA-DSGE economy, but
with all
households updating their knowledge of the aggregate state frictionlessly.
Critically, we do not actually calculate
each period; instead, we use the
same sequence of
that occurred in the ordinary sticky simulation. Thus our
simulated population of
households represents an infinitesimally small portion
of an economy made up (almost) entirely of consumers with sticky expectations.
The calculated
is thus the willingness-to-pay to be the very first agent to “wake
up”.
The formula for willingness-to-pay (31) arises from the homotheticity of the household’s
problem with respect to . If a consumer gives up an
portion of their permanent income
at the moment they are “born”, before receiving income that period, then his normalized
market resources will still be
, and he will make the same normalized
consumption choice that he would have, had he not lost any permanent income. In fact,
he will make the exact same sequence of normalized consumption choices for his
entire life; the level of his consumption will be scaled by the factor
in every
period. With CRRA utility, this means that utility is scaled by
in every
period of life, which can be factored out of the lifetime summation. The indifference
condition between being frictionless and losing an
fraction of permanent income
versus having sticky expectations (and not losing) can be easily rearranged into
(31).
This appendix derives the equation (3) asserted in the main text. Start with the definition of consumption for the updaters,
The text asserts (equation (3)) that
To see this, define market resources where
is noncapital income in
period
and
is the level of nonhuman assets with which the consumer ended the
previous period; and define
as ‘human wealth,’ the present discounted value of future
noncapital income. Then write
What theory tells us is that if aggregate consumption were chosen frictionlessly in period ,
then this expression would be white noise; that is, we know that
So equation (3) can be rewritten as
where
This appendix follows closely Appendix A in the ECB working paper version of Carroll
et al. [2015].66
It computes dynamics and steady state of the square of the idiosyncratic component of
permanent income (from which the variance can be derived). Recalling that consumers are
born with :
Finally, note the relation between and the variance of
:
For the preceding derivations to be valid, it is necessary to impose the parameter
restriction . This requires that income does not spread out so quickly among
survivors as to overcome the compression of the distribution that arises because of
death.
If the quarterly transitory shock is , define the annual transitory shock as:
Let be the quarterly permanent shock. Define the annual permanent shock as:
Muth [1960], pp. 303–304, shows that the signal-extracted estimate of permanent income is
This compares with (32) in the main text
Defining the signal-to-noise ratio , starting with equation (3.10) in Muth [1960]
we have