LiqConstr
______________________________________________________________________________________
Abstract
We provide the analytical explanation of strong interactions between precautionary saving and
liquidity constraints that are regularly observed in numerical solutions to consumption/saving models.
The effects of constraints and of uncertainty spring from the same cause: concavification of the
consumption function, which can be induced either by constraints or by uncertainty. Concavification
propagates back to consumption functions in prior periods. But, surprisingly, once a linear
consumption function has been concavified by the presence of either risks or constraints, the
introduction of additional concavifiers in a given period can reduce the precautionary motive in earlier
periods at some levels of wealth.
liquidity constraints, uncertainty, precautionary saving
C6, D91, E21
Repo: | https://github.com/llorracc/LiqConstr |
Web: | http://econ.jhu.edu/people/ccarroll/papers/LiqConstr/ |
Slides: | http://econ.jhu.edu/people/ccarroll/papers/LiqConstr/LiqConstr-Slides.pdf |
Econ-ARK: | http://github.com/Econ-ARK/REMARK/tree/master/REMARKs/LiqConstr.md |
Jupyter: | Live MyBinder.org Jupyter notebook producing the figures |
1Carroll: Department of Economics, Johns Hopkins University, email: ccarroll@jhu.edu
2Holm: Department of Economics, University of Oslo, email: martin.b.holm@outlook.com
3Kimball: Department of Economics, University of Colorado at Boulder, email: miles.kimball@colorado.edu
Numerical solutions have now supplanted analytical methods for modeling consumption/saving choices, because analytical solutions are not available for realistic descriptions of utility, uncertainty, and constraints.
A large literature in both micro and macroeconomics has demonstrated that numerical models that take constraints and uncertainty seriously can yield quite different conclusions than those obtainable for traditional models. For example, in heterogeneous agent New Keynesian models (e.g. Kaplan, Moll, and Violante, 2018), a major transmission mechanism for monetary policy is the indirect income effect because a substantial share of households have high marginal propensities to consume – a channel that is of minimal importance in perfect foresight unconstrained models. And Guerrieri and Lorenzoni (2017) and Bayer, Lütticke, Pham-Dao, and Tjaden (2019) show that tightened borrowing capacity and heightened income risk may be important explanatory factors behind the consumption decline during the great recession. Further, Krueger, Mitman, and Perri (2016) show that numerically realistic models can match the empirical finding that the drop in consumption spending during the great recession was heavily concentrated in the middle class.
But a drawback to numerical solutions is that it is often difficult to know why results come out the way they do. A leading example is in the complex relationship between precautionary saving behavior and liquidity constraints. At least since Zeldes (1984), economists working with numerical solutions have known that liquidity constraints can strictly increase precautionary saving under very general circumstances - even for consumers with a quadratic utility function that generates no intrinsic precautionary saving motive.1 On the other hand, simulation results have often found circumstances under which liquidity constraints and precautionary saving are substitutes rather than complements. In an early example, Samwick (1995) showed that unconstrained consumers with a precautionary saving motive in a retirement saving model behave in ways qualitatively and quantitatively similar to the behavior of liquidity constrained consumers facing no uncertainty.
This paper provides the theoretical tools to make sense of the interactions between liquidity constraints and precautionary saving. These tools provide a rigorous theoretical foundation that can be used to clarify the reasons for the numerical literature’s apparently contrasting findings.
For example, one of the paper’s main results is a proof that when a liquidity constraint is added to a standard consumption problem, the resulting value function exhibits increased ‘prudence’ (a greater precautionary motive) around the level of wealth where the constraint becomes binding.2 Constraints induce precaution because constrained agents have less flexibility in responding to shocks when the effects of the shocks cannot be spread out over time. We show that the precautionary motive is heightened by the desire (in the face of risk) to make future constraints less likely to bind.3
At a deeper level, we show that the effect of a constraint on prudence is an example of a general theoretical result: Prudence is induced by concavity of the consumption function. Since a constraint creates consumption concavity around the point where the constraint binds,4 adding a constraint necessarily boosts prudence around that point.5 We show that this concavity-boosts-prudence result holds for any utility function with non-negative third derivative; “prudence” in the utility function as in Kimball (1990) is not necessary, because prudence is created by consumption concavity.
These results connect closely to Carroll and Kimball (1996)’s demonstration that, within the HARA utility class, the introduction of uncertainty causes the consumption function to become strictly concave (in the absence of constraints) for all but a few knife-edge combinations of utility function and structure of risk. Taken together, this paper and Carroll and Kimball (1996) can be seen as establishing rigorously the sense in which precautionary saving and liquidity constraints are substitutes.6 To illustrate this point, we provide an example of a specific kind of uncertainty that (under CRRA utility, in the limit) induces a consumption function that is point-wise identical to the consumption function that would be induced by the addition of a liquidity constraint.
We further show that, once consumption concavity is created (by the introduction of either uncertainty or a constraint, or in any other way), it propagates back to periods before the period in which the concavity has been introduced.7 Precautionary saving is induced by the possibility that constraints might bind; this can explain why such a high percentage of households cite precautionary motives as the most important reason for saving (Kennickell and Lusardi, 1999) even though the fraction of households who report actually having been constrained in the past is relatively low (Jappelli, 1990).
Our final theoretical contribution is to show that the introduction of further liquidity constraints beyond the first one may actually reduce precautionary saving at some levels of wealth by ‘hiding’ the effects of the pre-existing constraint(s); they are no longer relevant because the liquidity constraint forces more saving than the precautionary motive would induce. Identical logic implies that uncertainty can ‘hide’ the effects of a constraint, because the consumer may save so much for precautionary reasons that the constraint becomes irrelevant. For example, a typical perfect foresight model of retirement consumption for a consumer with Social Security (guaranteed pension) income implies that a legal constraint on borrowing against benefits will cause the consumer to run assets down to zero, and thereafter set consumption equal to income. Now consider adding the possibility of large medical expenses near the end of life (e.g. nursing home fees; see Ameriks, Caplin, Laufer, and Van Nieuwerburgh, 2011). Under reasonable assumptions, a consumer facing such a risk may save enough for precautionary reasons to render the no-borrowing constraint irrelevant.
Our analysis proceeds in five steps. We present our general theoretical framework in the next section. We then show that consumption concavity increases prudence (Section 3); that concavity, once created, propagates to previous periods (Section 4); that constraints cause consumption concavity (Section 5); and when additional constraints or risks increase the precautionary saving motive (Section 6). The final section concludes.
Here we explain the setup intuitively
Consider a consumer who faces some future risks but is not subject to any current or future
liquidity constraints. The consumer is maximizing the time-additive present discounted value of
utility from consumption . With interest and time preference factors
and
, and labeling consumption
, stochastic labor income
, and gross wealth
(inclusive of period-t labor income)
, the consumer’s problem can be written as
| (1) |
with . Note that that (1) nests the case with quadratic utility
(
).
As usual, the recursive nature of the problem makes this equivalent to the Bellman equation:
We define
|
as the end-of-period value function where is the portion of period t resources saved. We can then
rewrite the problem as8
Here we explain prudence and consumption concavity intuitively
Our ultimate goal is to understand the relationship between liquidity constraints and precautionary saving. In this section we describe the relationship between consumption concavity and prudence; Kimball (1990) shows that prudence induces precautionary saving, and below we that consumption concavity is induced by either liquidity constraints or precautionary saving.
Our analysis of consumption concavity and prudence is couched in general terms and therefore applies whether the source of concavity is liquidity constraints or something else (e.g., uncertainty).9
Our approach shows that the crucial question is whether the value function exhibits a property we call consumption concavity (CC). So we define property CC first, and then we define a counterclockwise concavification which captures a specific class of transformations of a consumption function that make the modified function globally “more” concave.
Definition 1. (Local Consumption Concavity.)
In relation to a utility function with non-negative (
) and non-increasing
prudence, a function
has property CC (alternately, strict CC) over the interval
between
and
, where
, if
for some increasing function that satisfies concavity (alternately, strict concavity)
over the interval from
to
.
Since (even with constraints) holds by the envelope
theorem,
having property CC (alternately, strict CC) is the same
as having a concave (alternately, strictly concave) consumption function
.10
Note that the definition is restricted to non-negative and non-increasing prudence. This
encompasses most of the commonly used utility functions in the economics literature
(e.g. CRRA, CARA, quadratic). Also, note that we allow for ’non-strict’ concavity – that is,
linearity – because we want to encompass cases such as quadratic utility in which parts of the
consumption function can be linear. Henceforth, unless otherwise noted, we will drop the
cumbersome usage ’alternately, strict’ – the reader should assume that what we mean always
applies in the two alternate cases in parallel.
If a function has property CC at every point, we define it as having property CC globally.
Definition 2. (Global Consumption Concavity.)
A function has property CC in relation to a utility function
with
,
if
for some monotonically increasing concave function
.
We now show how consumption concavity affects the prudence of the value function. To compare two consumption functions and their respective concavity, we need to define when one function exhibits ‘greater’ concavity than another.
Definition 3. (Greater Consumption Concavity.)
Consider two functions and
that both exhibit property CC with respect to the
same
at a point
for some interval
such that
. Then
exhibits property ‘greater CC’ compared to
if
If and
exist everywhere between
and
, property CC is equivalent to
being weakly larger in absolute value than
everywhere in the range from
to
. The
strict version of the proposition would require the inequality to hold strictly over some interval
between
and
.
The next concept we introduce is ‘counterclockwise concavification,’ which describes an operation that makes the modified consumption function more concave than in the original situation. The idea is to think of the consumption function in the modified situation as being a twisted version of the consumption function in the baseline situation, where the kind of twisting allowed is a progressively larger increase in the MPC as the level of wealth gets lower. We call this a ‘counterclockwise concavification’ to capture the sense that at any specific level of wealth, one can think of the increase in the MPC at lower levels of wealth as being a counterclockwise rotation of the lower portion of the consumption function around that level of wealth.
Definition 4. (Counterclockwise Concavification.)
Function is a counterclockwise concavification of
around
if the following
conditions hold:
The limits are necessary to allow for the possibility of discrete drops in the MPC at potential ‘kink points’ in the consumption functions. To understand counterclockwise concavification, it is useful to derive its implied properties.
Lemma 1.(Properties of a Counterclockwise Concavification.)
If is a counterclockwise concavification of
around
and
for all
, then
See Appendix A for the proof. A counterclockwise concavification thus reduces consumption,
increases the MPC, and makes the consumption function more concave for all wealth levels
below the point of concavification. Figure 1 illustrates two examples of counterclockwise
concavifications: the introduction of a constraint and the introduction of a risk. In both cases,
we start from the situation with no risk or constraints (solid line). The introduction of a
constraint is a counterclockwise concavification around a kink point . Below
,
consumption is lower and the MPC is greater. The introduction of a risk also generates a
counterclockwise concavification of the original consumption function, but this time around
. For all
, consumption is lower, the MPC is higher, and the consumption function
is strictly more concave.
Notes: The solid line shows the linear consumption function in the case with no constraints and no risks. The
two dashed line show the consumption function when we introduce a constraint and a risk, respectively.
The introduction of a constraint is a counterclockwise concavification of the solid consumption
function around , while the introduction of a risk is a counterclockwise concavification around
.
The section above established all the tools necessary to show the relationship between
consumption concavity and prudence. Our method in this section is to compare prudence in a
baseline case where the consumption function is to prudence in a modified situation in
which the consumption function
is a counterclockwise concavification of the baseline
consumption function.
Our first result relates to the effects of a counterclockwise concavification on the absolute prudence of the value function.
Definition 5. (Absolute Prudence of the Value Function.)
Absolute prudence of the value function is defined as .
To understand the effects on prudence of a counterclockwise concavification, note that for a twice differentiable consumption function and thrice differentiable utility function, absolute prudence of the value function is defined as
| (3) |
by the envelope condition. The results we are about to derive in Theorem 1 then follow easily. Theorem 1 itself handles cases where the consumption function is not necessarily twice differentiable.
Theorem 1. (Counterclockwise Concavification and Prudence.)
Consider an agent who has a utility function with ,
,
, and
non-increasing absolute prudence (
). If
is concave and
is a
counterclockwise concavification of
, then the value function associated with
exhibits greater absolute prudence than the value function associated with
for all
.
See Appendix B for the proof. There are three channels through which a counterclockwise concavification heightens prudence. First, the increase in consumption concavity from the counterclockwise concavification itself heightens prudence. Second, if the absolute prudence of the utility function is non-increasing, then the reduction in consumption (in some states) from the counterclockwise concavification makes agents more prudent at those states. And third, the higher marginal propensity to consume (MPC) from the counterclockwise concavification means that any given variation in wealth results in larger variation in consumption, increasing prudence. The channels operate separately, implying that a counterclockwise concavification heightens prudence even if absolute prudence is zero as in the quadratic case.11
Theorem 1 only provides conditions for when the value function exhibits greater prudence,
but not strictly greater prudence. In particular, the value function associated with will in
some cases exhibit equal prudence for many values of
and strictly greater prudence only for
some values of
. In Corollary 1, we provide conditions for when the value function exhibits
strictly greater prudence.
Corollary 1. (Counterclockwise Concavification and Strictly Greater Prudence.)
Consider an agent who has a utility function with ,
,
, and
non-increasing absolute prudence (
). If
is concave and
is a
counterclockwise concavification of
around
, then the value function associated
with
exhibits strictly greater prudence than the value function associated with
if the utility function satisfies
and
or the utility function is quadratic
(
) and
strictly declines at
.
See Appendix C for the proof. For prudent agents (), the value function
exhibits strictly greater prudence for all levels of wealth where the counterclockwise
concavification affects consumption. This is because a reduction in consumption and
higher marginal propensity to consume heighten prudence if the utility function has a
positive third derivative and prudence is non-increasing. If the utility function instead
is quadratic, the third derivative is zero and the absolute prudence of the utility
function does not depend on the level of consumption or the marginal propensity to
consume. In this case, the counterclockwise concavification only affects prudence at
the kink points in the consumption function, i.e. where
strictly declines at
.
Section 3 defined conditions under which consumption concavity heightens prudence, by
comparing value functions and consumption functions at a specific point in time. In this
section, we provide conditions guaranteeing that if the consumption function is concave in
period , it will be concave in period
and earlier, whatever the source of that concavity
may be.
Theorem 2. (Recursive Propagation of Consumption Concavity.)
Consider an agent with a HARA utility function satisfying ,
,
and non-increasing absolute prudence (
). Assume that no liquidity
constraint applies at the end of period
and that the agent faces income risk
. If
exhibits property (local) consumption concavity for all
, then
exhibits property (local) consumption concavity
at the level of wealth
such that optimal consumption yields
.
If also exhibits property strict (local) consumption concavity for at least
one
, then
exhibits property strict (local) consumption
concavity at the level of wealth
where optimal consumption yields
.
See Appendix D for the proof. Theorem 2 presents conditions to ensure that the consumption
function is concave today if the consumption function is concave in the future. The basic insight
is that as long as the future consumption function is concave for all realizations of , then
it is also concave today. Additionally, if the the future consumption function is strictly concave
for at least one realization of
, then the consumption function is strictly concave also
today.
We now move on to the sources of consumption concavity. In our setting, there are two sources of consumption concavity: risk and constraints. The properties of consumption under risk have already been derived in Carroll and Kimball (1996). We therefore restrict our attention to showing how liquidity constraints make the consumption function concave. Once the relationship between liquidity constraints and consumption concavity is established, we use the results on consumption concavity and prudence to show under which conditions liquidity constraints heighten prudence.
Throughout this paper, we are working with a finite horizon household whose horizon goes from
to
. We define a liquidity constraint dated
as a constraint that requires savings at the
end of period
to be non-negative. The assumption of non-negativity is
without loss of generality; we show in Theorem 5 that our results also hold with general
constraints.
The timing of a constraint relative to other existing constraints matters for the effects of the constraint. We therefore need to define an ordered set to keep track of the existing constraints.
Definition 6. (The Set of Liquidity Constraints.)
We define as an ordered set of dates at which a relevant constraint exists. We define
as the last period in which a constraint exists,
as the date of the last period
before
in which a constraint exists, and so on.
is the set of relevant constraints, ordered from the last to the first constraint. We
order them from last to first because a constraint in period
only affects periods
prior to
. The set of constraints from period
to
summarizes all relevant
information in period
. Further, the effect of imposing one extra constraint on
consumption is unambiguous only if one imposes constraints chronologically from last to
first.
For any , we define
as the optimal consumption function in period
assuming that the first
constraints in
(in this chronologically backwards order)
have been imposed. For example,
is the consumption function in period
when no constraint (aside from the intertemporal budget constraint) has been
imposed,
is the consumption function in period
after the chronologically last
constraint has been imposed, and so on. We define
, and other functions
correspondingly.
To have a distinct terminology for the effects of current-period and future-period constraints, we will restrict the use of the term ‘binds’ to the potential effects of a constraint in the period in which it applies (‘the constraint binds if wealth is less than ...’) and will use the term ‘impinges’ to describe the effect of a future constraint on current consumption. We can now define the concept of a kink point.
Definition 7. (Kink Point.)
We define a kink point, as the level of wealth at which constraint
stops binding
or impinging on time
consumption.
A kink point corresponds to a transition from a level of wealth where a current constraint binds or a future constraint impinges, to a level of wealth where that constraint no longer binds or impinges.
We first consider an initial situation in which a consumer is solving a perfect foresight
optimization problem with a finite horizon that begins in period and ends in period
. The
consumer begins with wealth
and earns constant income
in each period. Wealth
accumulates according to
. We are interested in how this consumer’s behavior
in period
changes from an initial situation with
constraints to a situation in which
liquidity constraints has been imposed.
Theorem 3. (Perfect Foresight Consumption with Liquidity Constraints.)
Consider an agent who has a utility function with and
, faces constant
income
, and is impatient (
). Assume that the agent faces a set
of
relevant constraints. Then
is a counterclockwise concavification of
around
.
See Appendix E for the proof. Theorem 3 shows that when we have an ordered set of
constraints, , the introduction of the next constraint in the set generates a counterclockwise
concavification of the consumption function. Note that constraint
is always at a
date prior to the set of the first
constraints. From the proof of Theorem 3, we
also know the shape of the perfect foresight consumption function with liquidity
constraints:
Corollary 2. (Piecewise Linear Consumption Function.)
Consider an agent who has a utility function with and
, faces constant
income
, and is impatient. Assume that the agent faces a set
of
relevant
constraints. When
constraints have been imposed,
is a piecewise linear
increasing concave function with kink points at successively larger values of wealth at
which future constraints stop impinging on current consumption.
Since the consumption function is piecewise linear, the new consumption function,
is not necessarily strictly more concave than
for all
. This is where the concept of
counterclockwise concavification is useful. Even though
is not strictly more
concave than
everywhere, it is a counterclockwise concavification and we can
apply Theorem 1 to derive the consequences of imposing one more constraint on
prudence.
Theorem 4. (Liquidity Constraints Increase Prudence.)
Consider an agent in period who has a utility function with
,
,
and non-increasing absolute prudence (
), faces constant income
,
and is impatient,
. Assume that the agent faces a set
of
relevant
constraints. When
constraints have been imposed, the imposition of constraint
strictly increases absolute prudence of the agent’s value function if
and
or if
and
strictly declines at
.
Proof.By Theorem 3, the imposition of constraint constitutes a counterclockwise
concavification of
. By Theorem 1 and Corollary 1, such a concavification strictly
increases absolute prudence of the value function for the cases in Corollary 1. □
Theorem 4 is the main result in the current section: the introduction of the next liquidity constraint increases absolute prudence of the value function. In the subsequent discussions, we consider cases where we relax the assumptions underlying Theorem 4. We first consider the case where we add an extra constraint to the set of relevant constraints. Next, we consider the cases with time-varying deterministic income, general constraints, and no assumption on time discounting.
In the previous section, we analyzed a case where there was a preordained set of constraints
which were applied sequentially in reverse chronological order. We now examine how behavior
will be modified if we add a new date
to the set of dates at which the consumer is
constrained.
Call the new set of dates with
constraints (one more constraint than
before), and call the consumption rules corresponding to the new set of dates
through
. Now call
the number of constraints in
at dates strictly
greater than
. Then note that that
, because at dates after the date at
which the new constraint (number
) is imposed, consumption is the same as in
the absence of the new constraint. Now recall that imposition of the constraint at
causes a counterclockwise concavification of the consumption function around a
new kink point,
. That is,
is a counterclockwise concavification of
.
The most interesting observation, however, is that behavior under constraints in periods
strictly before
cannot be described as a counterclockwise concavification of behavior under
. The reason is that the values of wealth at which the earlier constraints caused kink points
in the consumption functions before period
will not generally correspond to kink points once
the extra constraint has been added.
Notes: is the original consumption function with one constraint that induces a kink point at
.
is
the modified consumption function in where we have introduced one new constraint. The two constraints affect
through two kink points:
and
. Since we introduced the new constraint at a later point in time
than the current existing constraint, the future constraint affects the position of the kink induced by the current
constraint and the modified consumption function
is not a counterclockwise concavification of
.
We present an example in Figure 2. The original contains only a single constraint, at the
end of period
, inducing a kink point at
in the consumption rule
. The
expanded set of constraints,
, adds one constraint at period
.
induces two kink
points in the updated consumption rule
, at
and
. It is true that imposition of
the new constraint causes consumption to be lower than before at every level of wealth below
. However, this does not imply higher prudence of the value function at every
. In particular, note that the original consumption function is strictly concave at
, while the new consumption function is linear at
, so prudence can be
greater before than after imposition of the new constraint at this particular level of
wealth.
The intuition is simple: At levels of initial wealth below , the consumer had been
planning to end period
with negative wealth. With the new constraint, the old plan of
ending up with negative wealth is no longer feasible and the consumer will save more for any
given level of current wealth below
, including
. But the reason
was a kink point
in the initial situation was that it was the level of wealth where consumption would have been
equal to wealth in period
. Now, because of the extra savings induced by the constraint in
, the larger savings induced by wealth
implies that the period
constraint will no longer bind for a consumer who begins period
with wealth
. In
other words, at wealth
the extra savings induced by the new constraint moves
the original constraint and prevents it from being relevant any more at the original
.
Notice, however, that all constraints that existed in will remain relevant at some level of
wealth under
even after the new constraint is imposed - they just induce kink points at
different levels of wealth than before, e.g. the first constraint causes a kink at
rather than
at
.
We now want to allow time variation in the level of income and in the location of the
liquidity constraint (e.g
a constraint in period
might require the consumer to end period
with savings
greater than
). We also drop the restriction that
, allowing the
consumer to desire consumption growth over time.
Under these more general circumstances, a constraint imposed in a given period can render
constraints in either earlier or later periods irrelevant. For example, consider a CRRA utility
consumer with who earns income of 1 in each period, but who is required to arrive at
the end of period
with savings of 5. Then a constraint that requires savings to be
greater than zero at the end of period
will have no effect because the consumer is
required by the constraint in period
to end period
with savings greater than
4.
Formally, consider now imposing the first constraint, which applies in period .
The simplest case, analyzed before, was a constraint that requires the minimum level of
end-of-period wealth to be
. Here we generalize this to
where in
principle we can allow borrowing by choosing
to be a negative number. Now for constraint
calculate the kink points for prior periods from
Now assume that the first constraints in
have been imposed, and consider
imposing constraint number
, which we assume applies at the end of period
. The first thing to check is whether constraint number
is relevant given
the already-imposed set of constraints. This is simple: A constraint that requires
will be irrelevant for all
if
, i.e. if one of the
existing constraints already implies that savings must be greater or equal to value
required by the new constraint. If the constraint is irrelevant then the analysis proceeds
simply by dropping this constraint and renumbering the constraints in
so that the
former constraint
becomes constraint
,
becomes
, and so
on.
Now consider the other possible problem: That constraint number imposed in period
will render irrelevant some of the constraints that have already been imposed. This too is
simple to check: It will be true if the proposed
for any
and for all
.13
The fix is again simple: Counting down from
, find the smallest value of
for which
. Then we know that constraint
has rendered constraints
through
irrelevant. The solution is to drop these constraints from
and start the analysis over again
with the modified
.
If this set of procedures is followed until the chronologically earliest relevant constraint has
been imposed, the result will be a that contains a set of constraints that can be analyzed as
in the simpler case. In particular, proceeding from the final
through
,
the imposition of each successive constraint in
now causes a counterclockwise
concavification of the consumption function around successively lower values of wealth as
progressively earlier constraints are applied and the result is again a piecewise linear
and strictly concave consumption function with the number of kink points equal to
the number of constraints that are relevant at any feasible level of wealth in period
.
The preceding discussion thus establishes the following result:
Theorem 5. (Liquidity Constraints Increase Prudence.)
Consider an agent in period who has a utility function with
,
,
, and non-increasing absolute prudence (
). Assume that the agent faces
a set
of
relevant constraints. When
constraints have been imposed,
the imposition of constraint
strictly increases absolute prudence of the agent’s
value function if the utility function satisfies
and
or if
and
strictly declines at
.
Theorem 5 is a generalization of Theorem 4. Even if we relax the assumptions that income is
constant and the agent is impatient, the imposition of an extra constraint increases absolute
prudence of the value function as long as we are careful when we select the set of relevant
constraints.
Finally, consider adding a new constraint to the problem and call the new set of constraints
. Suppose the new constraint applies in period
. Then the analysis of the new situation
will be like the analysis of an added constraint in the simpler case in section 5.3 if the new
constraint is relevant given the constraints that apply after period
and the new constraint
does not render any of those later constraints irrelevant. If the new constraint fails
either of these tests, the analysis of
can proceed from the ground up as described
above.
In the three previous sections, we have derived the relationships between liquidity constraints, consumption concavity, and prudence. It is now time to be explicit about the last step: the relationship between liquidity constraints and precautionary saving. We first explain the relationship between the precautionary premium and absolute prudence. We then use this result to show how the introduction of an additional constraint induces agents to increase precautionary saving when they face a current risk. Next, we explain why the result cannot be generalized to an added risk or liquidity constraint in a later time period. We end this section by showing our most general result on liquidity constraints and precautionary saving: The introduction of a risk has a greater precautionary effect in the presence of all future risks and constraints than in the absence of any future risks or constraints.
We begin by defining two marginal value functions and
which are convex,
downward sloping, and continuous in wealth,
. We consider a risk
with support
,
and follow Kimball (1990) by defining the Compensating Precautionary Premia (CPP) as the
values
and
such that
Lemma 2.Let and
be absolute prudence of the value functions
and
respectively
at
,14
and let
and
be the respective compensating precautionary premia associated with
imposition of a given risk
as per (7) and (8). Then the following conditions are
equivalent:
Lemma 2 thus establishes that exhibiting greater prudence is equivalent to inducing a greater precautionary premium. For our purpose, it means that our results above on the absolute prudence also imply that the precautionary premium is higher, i.e. that a more prudent consumer would require a higher compensation to be indifferent about accepting the risk.15
We now take up the question of how the introduction of a risk that will be realized at
the beginning of period
affects consumption in period
in the presence and in the
absence of a subsequent constraint. To simplify the discussion, consider a consumer for whom
, with mean income
in period
.
Assume that the realization of the risk will be some value
with support [
,
], and
signify a decision rule that takes account of the presence of the immediate risk by a
. Thus,
the perfect foresight unconstrained consumption function is
, the perfect foresight
consumption function in the presence of the constraint is
, the consumption function
with no constraint but with the risk is
and the consumption function with both the
risk and the constraint is
. (Corresponding notation applies to the other
functions below). We now define the level of wealth such that liquidity constraint
never binds for a consumer facing the risk whose wealth is higher than that
limit:
Definition 8. (Wealth Limit.)is the level of wealth such that an agent who faces risk
and
constraints
saves enough to guarantee that constraint
will never bind in period
. Its value is
given by:
We must be careful to check that is inside the realm of feasible values of
, in the sense of values that permit the consumer to guarantee that future levels
of consumption will be within the permissible range (e.g. positive for consumers
with CRRA utility). If this is not true for some level of wealth, then any constraint
that binds at or below that level of wealth is irrelevant, because the restriction on
wealth imposed by the risk is more stringent than the restriction imposed by the
constraint.
We are now in the position to analyze the relationship between precautionary saving and
liquidity constraints. Our first result regards the effect of an additional constraint on the
precautionary saving of a household facing risk at the beginning of period (before any
choices are made in that period).
Theorem 6. (Precautionary Saving with Liquidity Constraints.)
Consider an agent who has a utility function with ,
,
, and
non-increasing absolute prudence (
), and who faces the risk,
. Assume that the
agent faces a set
of N relevant constraints and
. Then
| (10) |
and the inequality is strict if wealth is less than the level that ensures that the last constraint
never binds ().
See Appendix F for the proof. Theorem 6 shows that the introduction of the next constraint
induces the agent to save more for precautionary reasons in response to an immediate risk as
long as there is a positive probability that the next constraint will bind. Theorem 6 can be
generalized to period if there is no risk or constraint between period
and
: We
simply define
as the wealth level at which the agent will arrive in the beginning of
period
with wealth
.
To illustrate the result in Theorem 6, Figure 3 shows an example of optimal consumption
rules in period under different combinations of an immediate risk (realized at the beginning
of period
) and a future constraint (applying at the end of period
).
Notes: is the consumption function with no constraint and no risk,
is the consumption function with
no constraint and a risk that is realized at the beginning of period
,
is the consumption function
with one constraint in period
and no risk, and
is the consumption function with one constraint in
period
and a risk that is realized at the beginning of period
. The figure illustrates that the vertical
distance between
and
is always greater than the vertical distance between
and
for
.
The thinner loci reflect behavior of consumers who face the future constraint, and the dashed
loci reflect behavior of consumers who face the immediate risk. For levels of wealth above
where the future constraint stops impinging on current behavior for perfect foresight
consumers, behavior of the constrained and unconstrained perfect foresight consumers is the
same. Similarly,
for levels of wealth above
beyond which the
probability of the future constraint binding is zero. For both constrained and unconstrained
consumers, the introduction of the risk reduces the level of consumption (the dashed loci are
below their solid counterparts). The significance of Theorem 6 in this context is that for levels
of wealth below
, the vertical distance between the solid and the dashed loci is greater
for the constrained (thin line) than for the unconstrained (thick line) consumers,
because of the interaction between the liquidity constraint and the precautionary
motive.
The result in Theorem 6 is limited to the effects of an additional constraint when a household
faces income risk that is realized at the beginning of period . Intuition might suggest that
this could be generalized to a proposition that precautionary saving increases if we for
example impose an immediate constraint or an earlier risk, or generally impose multiple
constraints or risks. However, it turns out that the answer is “not necessarily” to all these
possible scenarios. In this subsection, we explain why we cannot derive more general
results.
To describe these results, we need to develop a last bit of notation. We define, , as the
consumption function in period
assuming that the first
constraints and the first
risks have been imposed, counting risks, like constraints, backwards from period
. Thus, relating our new notation to our previous usage,
because 0
risks have been imposed. All other functions are defined correspondingly, e.g.
is the end-of-period-
value function assuming the first
constraints and
risks have been imposed. We will continue to use the notation
to designate the
effects of imposition of a single immediate risk (realized at the beginning of period
).
Suppose now there are future risks that will be realized between
and
. One might
hope to show that, at any
, the precautionary effect of imposing all risks in the presence of
all constraints would be greater than the effect of imposing all risks in the absence of any
constraints:
| (11) |
Such a hope, however, would be in vain. In fact, we will now show that even the
considerably weaker condition, involving only the single risk and all constraints,
can fail to hold for some
.
Consider a situation in which constraints apply in between
and
. Since
designates the consumption rule that will be optimal prior to imposing the period-
constraint, the consumption rule imposing all constraints will be
Consider now the question of how the addition of a risk that will be realized at the
beginning of period
affects the consumption function at the beginning of period
, in
the absence of any constraint at the beginning of period
.
The question at hand is then whether we can say that
that is, does the introduction of the riskThe answer again is “not necessarily.” To see why, we present an example in Appendix G of a
CRRA utility problem in which in a certain limit the introduction of a risk produced
an effect on the consumption function that is indistinguishable from the effect of a
liquidity constraint. If the risk is of this liquidity-constraint-indistinguishable
form, then the logic of the previous subsection applies: For some levels of wealth, the
introduction of the risk at
can weaken the precautionary effect of any risks at
or
later.
It might seem that the previous subsection implies that little useful can be said about the precautionary effects of introducing a new risk in the presence of preexisting constraints and risks. It turns out, however, that there is at least one strong result.
Theorem 7. Consider an agent who has a utility function with ,
,
,
and non-increasing absolute prudence (
). Then the introduction of a risk
has a
greater precautionary effect on period
consumption in the presence of all future
risks and constraints than in the absence of any future risks and constraints, i.e.
Appendix H presents the proof. It seems to us that a fair summary of this theorem is that in most circumstances the presence of future constraints and risks does increase the amount of precautionary saving induced by the introduction of a given new risk. The primary circumstance under which this should not be expected is for levels of wealth at which the consumer was constrained even in the absence of the new risk. There is no guarantee that the new risk will produce a sufficiently intense precautionary saving motive to move the initially-constrained consumer off his constraint. If it does, the effect will be precautionary, but it is possible that no effect will occur.
The central message of this paper is that the effects of liquidity constraints and future risks on precautionary saving are very similar because the introduction of either a liquidity constraints or of a risk induce a ‘counterclockwise concavification’ of the consumption function. No matter how it is caused, such an increase in concavity increases prudence and makes agents save more for precautionary reasons.
In addition, we provide an explanation of the apparently contradictory results that have
emerged from simulation studies, which have sometimes seemed to indicate that constraints
intensify precautionary saving motives (they are complements), and sometimes have found
constraints and precautionary behavior are substitutes. The insight here is that the
outcome at any given depends on whether the introduction of a constraint or
risk weakens the effects of any preexisting constraints or risks. If the new constraint
or risk does not interact in any way with existing constraints or risks, it intensifies
the precautionary saving motive. If it ‘hides’ or moves the effects of any existing
constraints or risks, it might weaken the precautionary saving motive at the given
.
Ameriks, John, Andrew Caplin, Steven Laufer, and Stijn Van Nieuwerburgh (2011): “The Joy Of Giving Or Assisted Living? Using Strategic Surveys To Separate Public Care Aversion From Bequest Motives,” The Journal of Finance, 66(2), 519–561.
Bayer, Christian, Ralph Lütticke, Lien Pham-Dao, and Volker Tjaden (2019): “Precautionary savings, illiquid assets, and the aggregate consequences of shocks to household income risk,” Econometrica, 87(1), 255–290.
Beckenbach, Edwin F, and Richard Bellman (1983): Inequalities, vol. 30. Springer, reprint edn.
Carroll, Christopher D., and Miles S. Kimball (1996): “On the Concavity of the Consumption Function,” Econometrica, 64(4), 981–992, http://econ.jhu.edu/people/ccarroll/concavity.pdf.
Deaton, Angus S. (1991): “Saving and Liquidity Constraints,” Econometrica, 59, 1221–1248, http://www.jstor.org/stable/2938366.
Druedahl, Jeppe, and Casper Nordal Jørgensen (2018): “Precautionary borrowing and the credit card debt puzzle,” Quantitative Economics, 9(2), 785–823.
Fernandez-Corugedo, Emilio (2000): “Soft Liquidity Constraints and Precautionary Savings,” Manuscript, Bank of England.
Fulford, Scott L (2015): “How important is variability in consumer credit limits?,” Journal of Monetary Economics, 72, 42–63.
Guerrieri, Veronica, and Guido Lorenzoni (2017): “Credit crises, precautionary savings, and the liquidity trap,” The Quarterly Journal of Economics, 132(3), 1427–1467.
Holm, Martin Blomhoff (2018): “Consumption with liquidity constraints: An analytical characterization,” Economics Letters, 167, 40–42.
Jappelli, Tullio (1990): “Who is Credit Constrained in the U.S. Economy?,” Quarterly Journal of Economics, 105(1), 219–34.
Kaplan, Greg, Benjamin Moll, and Giovanni L. Violante (2018): “Monetary Policy According to HANK,” American Economic Review, 108(3), 697–743.
Kennickell, Arthur B., and Annamaria Lusardi (1999): “Assessing the Importance of the Precautionary Saving Motive: Evidence from the 1995 SCF,” Manuscript, Board of Governors of the Federal Reserve System.
Kimball, Miles S. (1990): “Precautionary Saving in the Small and in the Large,” Econometrica, 58, 53–73.
Krueger, Dirk, Kurt Mitman, and Fabrizio Perri (2016): “Macroeconomics and Household Heterogeneity,” Handbook of Macroeconomics, 2, 843–921.
Lee, Jeong-Joon, and Yasuyuki Sawada (2007): “The degree of precautionary saving: A reexamination,” Economics Letters, 96(2), 196–201.
(2010): “Precautionary saving under liquidity constraints: Evidence from rural Pakistan,” Journal of Development Economics, 91(1), 77–86.
Mendelson, Haim, and Yakov Amihud (1982): “Optimal Consumption Policy Under Uncertain Income,” Management Science, 28(6), 683–697.
Nishiyama, Shin-Ichi, and Ryo Kato (2012): “On the Concavity of the Consumption Function with a Quadratic Utility under Liquidity Constraints,” Theoretical Economics Letters, 2(05), 566.
Park, Myung-Ho (2006): “An analytical solution to the inverse consumption function with liquidity constraints,” Economics Letters, 92(3), 389–394.
Pratt, John W. (1964): “Risk Aversion in the Small and in the Large,” Econometrica, 32, 122–136.
Samwick, Andrew A. (1995): “The Limited Offset Between Pension Wealth and Other Private Wealth: Implications of Buffer-Stock Saving,” Manuscript, Department of Economics, Dartmouth College.
Seater, John J (1997): “An optimal control solution to the liquidity constraint problem,” Economics Letters, 54(2), 127–134.
Zeldes, Stephen P. (1984): “Optimal Consumption with Stochastic Income,” Ph.D. thesis, Massachusetts Institute of Technology.
Proof.First, condition 2 and 4 in Definition 4 imply that for
for a small
. Condition 3 then ensures that
holds
for all
(equivalently
). Second, condition 1 and the fact that
for
implies that
for
. Third, condition 3 in Definition 4 implies that
Proof. By the envelope theorem, we know that
Differentiating with respect to yields
| (15) |
Since is concave, it has left-hand and right-hand derivatives at every point, though the
left-hand and right-hand derivatives may not be equal. Equation (15) should be interpreted as
applying the left-hand and right-hand derivatives separately. (Reading (15) in this way implies
that
; therefore
). Taking another derivative can run afoul
of the possible discontinuity in
that we will show below can arise from liquidity
constraints. We therefore consider two cases: (i)
exists and (ii)
does not
exist.
Case I: ( exists.)
In the case where exists, we can take another derivative
Absolute prudence of the value function is thus defined as
From the assumption that is a counterclockwise concavification of
,
we know from Lemma 1 that
and
. Furthermore, since
is non-increasing, we know that
. As a result,
.
The second part of the absolute prudence expression, , is a measure of the curvature of
the consumption function. Since the consumption function is concave,
is a measure of the
degree of concavity. Formally, if one has two functions,
and
, that are both increasing
and concave functions, then the concave transformation
always has more curvature than
.16 A
counterclockwise concavification is an example of such a
. Hence,
.
Then
Case II: ( does not exist.)
Informally, if nonexistence is caused by a constraint binding at , the effect will be a discrete
decline in the marginal propensity to consume at
, which can be thought of as
, implying positive infinite prudence at that point (see (16)). Formally, if
does not exist, greater prudence of
than
is given by
being a decreasing function
of
. This is defined as
The second factor, , is weakly decreasing in
by the property of a counterclockwise
concavification. At any specific value of
where
does not exist because
the left and right hand values of
are different, we say that
is decreasing if
As for the first factor, note that nonexistence of and/or
do not spring from
nonexistence of either
or
(for our purposes, when the left and right
derivatives of
differ at a point, the relevant derivative is the one coming from the left;
rather than carry around the cumbersome limit notation, read the following derivation as
applying to the left derivative). To discover whether
is decreasing we differentiate
(recall that the log is a monotonically decreasing transformation so the
derivative of the log of a function always has the same sign as the derivative of the
function):
This will be negative if
Recall from Lemma 1 that and
so non-increasing absolute
prudence of the utility function ensures that
. Hence the LHS is always
greater or equal to the RHS of equation (18).
□
Proof.We prove each statement in Corollary 1 separately.
Case I: (.)
If , a counterclockwise concavification around
implies that
and
for all
. Then
Note that this condition is sufficient to prove Corollary 1 for the case where does
not exist since it then satisfies (18). In the case where
does exist, we know that
from the proof of Theorem 1. Hence,
and Corollary 1 holds in the case with and
.
Case II: (.)
The quadratic case requires a different approach. Note first that the conditions in Corollary 1
hold only below the bliss point for quadratic utility. In addition, since , strict
inequality between the prudence of
and the prudence of
hold only at those points where
is strictly concave.
Recall from the proof of Theorem 1 that greater prudence of than
occurs if
is decreasing in
. In the quadratic case
| (19) |
where the second equality follows since is constant with quadratic utility. Thus,
prudence is strictly greater in the modified case only if
strictly declines in
. □
Proof.First, to facilitate readability of the proof, we assume that with
no loss of generality. Our goal is to prove that
if
for all realizations of
. The proof proceeds in two steps. First, we show that
property CC is preserved through the expectation operator (vertical aggregation),
i.e. that
if
for all realizations
of
. Second, we show that property CC is preserved through the value function
operator (horizontal aggregation), i.e. that
if
. Throughout the proof, the first order condition holds with equality since
no liquidity constraint applies at the end of period
.
Step 1: Vertical aggregation
We show that consumption concavity is preserved under vertical aggregation for three cases of
the HARA utility function with (
) and non-increasing absolute prudence
(
). The three cases are
| (20) |
Case I (, CRRA.) We will show that concavity is preserved under vertical aggregation
for
to avoid clutter, but the results hold for all affine transformations,
, with
. Concavity of
implies that
| (21) |
for all if
with
. Since this holds for all
, we
know that
We now apply Minkowski’s inequality (see e.g. Beckenbach and Bellman, 1983, Theorem 3)
which says that for and a scalar
This implies that for (CRRA)
if and
. Thus
which implies that
Thus, defining , we get
for all , where the inequality is strict if
is strictly concave for at least one realization
of
.
Case II (, CARA). For the exponential case, property CC holds at
if
Now consider a value of for which
is strictly concave for at least one
realization of
. Global weak concavity of
tells us that for every
Meanwhile, the arithmetic-geometric mean inequality states that for positive and
, if
and
, then
|
implying that
|
where the expression holds with equality only if is proportional to
. Substituting in
and
, this means that
Case III (, Quadratic). In the quadratic case, linearity of marginal utility implies
that
Step 2: Horizontal aggregation:
We now proceed with horizontal aggregation, namely how concavity is preserved through the
value function operation. Assume that at point
, then the first order condition
implies that
for some monotonically increasing that satisfies
for any , and
.
In addition, we know that the first order condition holds with equality such that
which implies that
. Using this equation, we
get
which implies that is a convex function.
Use the budget constraint to define
Now, since is a convex function, and
is the sum of a convex and a linear
function, it is also a convex function satisfying
so is concave.
Note that the proof of horizontal aggregation works for any utility function with and
when
=
= 1. However, for the more general case where
or
are not equal
to one, we need the HARA property that multiplying
by a constant corresponds to a linear
transformation of
.
Strict Consumption Concavity. When exhibits the property strict
consumption concavity for at least one
, we know that
also exhibits the property strict consumption concavity from the proof of
vertical aggregation. Then, equation (25) holds with strict inequality, and this strict
inequality goes through the proof of horizontal aggregation, implying that equation (26)
holds with strict inequality. Hence,
is strictly concave if
is
concave for all realizations of
and strictly concave for at least one realization of
. □
We prove Theorem 3 by induction in two steps. First, we show that all results in Theorem 3
hold when we add the first constraint. The second step is then to show that the results hold
when we go from to
constraints.
Lemma 3.
Consider an agent who has a utility function with and
, faces constant
income, is impatient (
), and has a finite life. Then
.
Proof.The marginal propensity to consume in period can be obtained from the MPC in
period
from the Euler equation
Furthermore, we know that
since is the MPC for an infinitely-lived agent with
. Hence,
and it follows that . □
Lemma 4.(Consumption with one Liquidity Constraint.)
Consider an agent who has a utility function with and
, faces constant
income,
, and is impatient,
. Assume that the agent faces a set
of one
relevant constraint. Then
is a counterclockwise concavification of
around
.
Proof.We now prove Lemma 4 by first showing that the consumption function
including the constraint at the end of period is a counterclockwise concavification
of the unconstrained consumption function in period
. Next, we show how the
constraint further implies that the consumption function including the constraint is a
counterclockwise concavification of the unconstrained consumption function in periods
prior to
.
We first define as the time period of the constraint. Note first that consumption is
unaffected by the constraint for all periods after
, i.e.
for any
. For
period
, we can calculate the level of consumption at which the constraint binds by realizing
that a consumer for whom the constraint binds will save nothing and therefore arrive in
the next period with no wealth. Further, the maximum amount of consumption at
which the constraint binds will satisfy the Euler equation (only points where the
constraint is strictly binding violate the Euler equation; the point on the cusp does not).
Thus, we define
as the maximum level of consumption in period
at which
the agent leaves no wealth for the next period, i.e. the constraint stops binding:
Below this level of wealth, we have so the MPC is one, while above it we have
where the MPC equals the constant MPC for an unconstrained perfect
foresight optimization problem with a horizon of
. Thus,
satisfies our definition of a
counterclockwise concavification of
around
.
Further, we can obtain the value of period consumption at which the period
constraint stops impinging on period
behavior from
Now consider the behavior of a consumer in period with a level of wealth
. This consumer knows he will be constrained and will spend all of his resources
next period, so at
his behavior will be identical to the behavior of a consumer whose entire
horizon ends at time
. As shown in step I, the MPC always declines with horizon. The MPC
for this consumer is therefore strictly greater than the MPC of the unconstrained consumer
whose horizon ends at
. Thus, in each period before
, the consumption
function
generated by imposition of the constraint constitutes a counterclockwise
concavification of the unconstrained consumption function around the kink point
. □
We have now shown the results in Theorem 3 for . The last step is to show that they
also hold for
when they hold strictly for
. Consider imposing the
’st constraint
and suppose for concreteness that it applies at the end of period
. It will stop binding at a
level of consumption defined by
The prior-period levels of consumption and wealth at which constraint stops
impinging on consumption can again be calculated recursively from
Furthermore, once again we can think of the constraint as terminating the horizon of a
finite-horizon consumer in an earlier period than it is terminated for the less-constrained
consumer, with the implication that the MPC below is strictly greater than the MPC
above
. Thus, the consumption function
constitutes a counterclockwise
concavification of the consumption function
around the kink point
.
Proof.
Our proof proceeds by constructing the behavior of consumers facing the risk from the
behavior of the corresponding perfect foresight consumers. We consider matters from the
perspective of some level of wealth for the perfect foresight consumers. Because the same
marginal utility function
applies to all four consumption rules, the Compensating
Precautionary Premia,
and
, associated with the introduction of the risk
must satisfy
We can rewrite (29) (resp. (28)) as
If we can show that (32) is a positive number for all feasible levels of
satisfying
, then we have proven Theorem 6. We know that
the marginal propensity to consume is always strictly positive and that
17
so to prove that (32) is strictly positive, we need to show one of two sufficient conditions:
Now, since , we know that
from Jensen’s inequality. Hence,
since
. The first integral in (32) is therefore strictly positive as long as
,
which is true for
by Theorem 3.
For , we know that
so the first integral in (32) is always
zero. For the second integral in (32) to be strictly positive, we need to show that
.
First define the perfect foresight consumption functions as
whereNow recall that Lemma 2 tells us that if absolute prudence of is identical to
absolute prudence of
for every realization of
, then
. This is
true if
for all possible realizations of
, i.e. that the agent is
unconstrained for all realizations of the risk. We defined this limit as
. We
therefore know that
if
.
For all levels of wealth below this limit (), there exist realizations of
such
that constraint
will bind in period
. The agent will require a higher precautionary
premia when facing constraint
in addition to the
constraints already in the set,
implying that
. Equation (32) is therefore strictly positive if
and
we have proven Theorem 6.
□
In this appendix, we provide an example where the introduction of risk resembles the
introduction of a constraint. Consider the second-to-last period of life for two risk-averse CRRA
utility consumers and assume for simplicity that .
The first consumer is subject to a liquidity constraint , and earns
non-stochastic income of
in period
. This consumer’s saving rule will be
|
The second consumer is not subject to a liquidity constraint, but faces a stochastic income process,
|
If we write the consumption rule for the unconstrained consumer facing the risk as
the key result is that in the limit as
, behavior of the two consumers becomes the same.
That is, defining
as the optimal saving rule for the consumer facing the
risk,
|
for every .
To see this, start with the Euler equations for the two consumers given wealth ,
Consider first the case where is large enough that the constraint does not bind for the
constrained consumer,
. In this case the limit of the Euler equation for the
second consumer is identical to the Euler equation for the first consumer (because for
savings are positive for the consumer facing the risk, implying that the limit of
the first
term on the RHS of (36) is finite). Thus the limit of (36) is (35) for
.
Now consider the case where so that the first consumer would be constrained. This
consumer spends her entire resources
, and by the definition of the constraint we know that
Now consider the consumer facing the risk. If this consumer were to save exactly
zero and then experienced the bad shock in period , she would have an infinite
marginal utility (the Inada condition). This cannot satisfy the Euler-equation as long as
. Therefore we know that for any
and any
the consumer will save
some positive amount. For a fixed
, hypothesize that there is some
such
that no matter how small
became the consumer would always choose to save
at least
. But for any
, the limit of the RHS of (36) is
. We know
from concavity of the utility function that
and we know from (37)
that
, so as
there must always come a point at
which the consumer can improve her total utility by shifting some resources from the
future to the present, i.e. by saving less. Since this argument holds for any
it
demonstrates that as
goes to zero there is no positive level of saving that would make the
consumer better off. But saving of zero or a negative amount is ruled out by the
Inada condition at
. Hence saving must approach, but never equal, zero as
.
Thus, we have shown that for and for
in the limit as
the
consumer facing the risk but no constraint behaves identically to the consumer facing the
constraint but no risk. This argument can be generalized to show that for the CRRA
utility consumer, spending must always be strictly less than the sum of current wealth
and the minimum possible value of human wealth. Thus, the addition of a risk to
the problem can rule out certain levels of wealth as feasible, and can also render
either future or past constraints irrelevant, just as the imposition of a new constraint
can.
Proof.To simplify notation and without loss of generality, we assume that when an agent
faces constraints and
risks, there are one constraint and one risk for each time
period. For example, if
faces
future risks and
future constraints, then the next
period consumption function is
(and
). Note that we can transform any
problem into this notation by filling in with degenerate risks and non-binding constraints.
However, for Theorem 7 to hold with strict inequality, we need to assume that there is
at least one relevant future risk and one relevant constraint.
We know that either the introduction of risk or a introduction of a constraint results in a counterclockwise concavification of the original consumption function. However, this is only true when we introduce risks in the absence of constraints (see Carroll and Kimball, 1996) and when we introduce constraints in the absence of risk (see Theorem 4). In this proof, we therefore need to show that the introduction of all risks and constraints is a counterclockwise concavification of the linear case with no risks and constraints.
Here is our proof strategy. We define a set
where Theorem 7 holds in period when we introduce a risk at the beginning of period
. This is defined as the set where precautionary saving induced by a risk that is realized
at the beginning of period
is greater in the presence of all risks and constraints than in
the unconstrained case.
In order to show that the set is non-empty, we build it up recursively, starting from
period
and adding one constraint or one risk for each time period. The key to the proof is
to understand that the introduction of risks or constraints will never fully reverse the effects of
all other risks and constraints, even though they sometimes reduce absolute prudence for some
levels of wealth because risks and constraints can mask the effects of future risks and
constraints. Hence, the new consumption function must still be a counterclockwise
concavification of the consumption function with no risks and constraints for some levels of
wealth.
Since a counterclockwise concavification increases prudence by Theorem 1, and higher prudence increases precautionary saving by Lemma 2, our required set can be redefined as
where we add the last condition, to avoid the possibility that some constraint
binds such that the agent does not increase precautionary saving. In words:
is the set
where the consumption function is a counterclockwise concavification of
and no
constraint is strictly binding. We construct the set recursively for two different cases:
CARA and all other type of utility functions. We start with the non-CARA utility
functions.
First add the last constraint. The set is then
since we know that is a counterclockwise concavification of
around
but
that the consumer is constrained below this point.
We next add the risk at the beginning of period . To construct the new set, we note three
things. First, by Theorem 2, (strict) consumption concavity is recursively propagated for all
values of wealth where there is a positive probability that the constraint can bind,
i.e.
has property strict CC, while it has non-strict property for all possible values of
.
Further, we know from Theorem 6 (rearrange equation (10)) that
Third, we know that since
for
,
, and that
is concave while
is linear.
Hence,
is a counterclockwise concavification of
around the minimum value of
wealth when the constraint will never bind and the new set is
We can now add the next constraint. The consumption function now has two kink points,
and
. We know again from Theorem 2 that consumption concavity is preserved
when we add a constraint, and strict consumption concavity is preserved for all values of
wealth at which a future constraint might bind. Further, we know from Theorem 6
that
Third, ,
, and we know that if
is concave while
is linear, then
.
which
is a counterclockwise concavification of
around the minimum level of wealth at
which the first constraint will never impinge on time
consumption,
, and the
new set is
It is now time to add the next risk. The argument is similar. We still know that (strict)
consumption concavity is recursively propagated and that .
Further, we can think of the addition of two risks over two periods as adding one risk that is
realized over two periods. Hence, the results from Theorem 6 must hold also for the addition of
multiple risks so we have
Hence, we again know that .
is thus a counterclockwise
concavification of
around the level of wealth at minimum value of wealth when the
last constraint will never bind. The new set is therefore
Doing this recursively and defining as the minimum value of wealth beyond which
constraint
will never bind, the set of wealth levels at which Theorem 7 holds can be defined
as
In words, precautionary saving is higher if there is a positive probability that some future constraint could bind and the consumer is not constrained today.
The last requirement is to define the set also for the CARA utility function. The problem
with CARA utility is that where
is some
positive constant. We can therefore not use the same arguments as in the preceding
proof. However, by realizing that equation (10) in the CARA case can be defined
as
where the last inequality follows since precautionary saving is always higher than in the constant limit in the presence of constraints. We can therefore rearrange to get
which implies that the arguments in the preceding section goes through also for CARA utility with this slight modification. □